An Early Modern South Asian Thinker on the Rise and Decline of Empires: Sh h Wal All h of Delhi, the Mughals, and the Byzantines

Vasileios Syros, Finnish Center of Political Thought , and Conceptual

 Change/ , Humboldt-Universität zu Berlin

In the eighteenth century, Western intellectual history witnessed the production of a rich body of writing on the origins and decay of  human civilization and the emergence and fall of empires, exemplified  by such monumental works as Baron de Montesquieu’s (1689–1755)  Considérations sur les causes de la grandeur des Romains et de leur déca dence (Reflections on the Causes of the Greatness of the Romans and  Their Decline, 1734), Giambattista Vico’s (1668–1744) Scienza Nuova (New Science, 1745), and Edward Gibbon’s (1737–1794) History of  the Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire (1776–1788). The quest to  identify the forces that shape social evolution and the factors involved  in the formation and decline of the state is not a phenomenon unique  to the Western intellectual scene, however. In the eighteenth-century  Mughal  context,  Shāh  Walī  Allāh  Dihlawī  (1703–1762), an eminent Sufi and theologian, propounded a theory of civilization and the  origins and downfall of social organization that has much in common  with Montesquieu’s, Vico’s, and Gibbon’s models and lends itself, as I  will show, to a cross-cultural study of ideas on imperial formation and  decay.1

Shāh  Walī  Allāh’s  father,  Shah  ‘Abd  ar-Rahīm  (1646–1719),  was  one  of  the  founders  and  teachers  of  the  Madrasah-i-Raḥīmīyah  in Delhi.2 Shāh Walī Allāh received his early education in the tafsīr,  hadīth, Qu’ranic sciences, and logic from his father. He subsequently  taught at his father’s school and then left for Arabia in 1730 to pursue  higher education. When he returned to Delhi in 1732, he worked to  spread knowledge about Islam, attracted a number of illustrious disciples, and produced a number of writings in Persian and Arabic. While  the bulk of his oeuvre is devoted to theological questions, in certain  sections of his principal philosophical works, notably the Ḥujjat Allāh  al-Bālighah (The Conclusive Argument from God)3 and his Al-Budūr  al-Bāzighah (The Full Moon Rising on the Horizon),4 he formulates an  intriguing theory about the genesis of human civilization and the decay  of social organization.

A substantial body of literature on Shāh Walī Allāh’s political doc trines exists. But his theory of empire has been much misunderstood  or neglected, due to a persistent tendency of previous scholarship to  extrapolate and reconstruct Shāh Walī Allāh’s ideas on the “decline”  of the Mughal Empire by focusing on his vitriolic polemic against the  proliferation of Hindu practices as expressed in his letters and portray  Shāh Walī Allāh  as  an  ardent  apologist  of jihād in the South Asian  context.5 

One of the main purposes of this paper is to show that Shāh Walī  Allāh’s position is much more complex than has been hitherto assumed.  I propose to challenge the standard reading of Shāh Walī Allāh’s pri vate writings as mere jeremiads against Hindu influences or part of a  program designed to invigorate or revivify Islamic rule in a state ener vated by constant conflicts. In particular, I call attention to certain  aspects of his political theory as set forth in his philosophical treatises,  and I argue that he pursues an agenda that is not confined to the political and social realities that prevailed in late Mughal India. Although  I do not mean  to dissociate Shāh Walī Allāh’s private writings from  his philosophical works and will occasionally include references to  his letters, my goal is to uncover the broader political program that  he articulates, one that extends beyond Mughal political realities. As  such, my analysis contrasts sharply with the traditional image of Shāh  Walī Allāh as the representative of a rabid trend of anti-Hinduism and  the harbinger of revivalist movements in South Asia.6 I show that his  rationalistic approach to the dynamics of social life and mechanics of  power reflects a nuanced understanding of the process of state7 forma tion that heretofore has not found its due place in modern narratives  of imperial state building and decline.8 In the first section of my article, I discuss how Shāh Walī Allāh’s  theory of the state relates to a broader scheme about the emergence and  evolution of civilization. In particular, I focus on his ideas on the origin  of communal life, the constituents of efficient rulership, the duties and  attributes of a rightful ruler, the modes of conduct necessary to preserve  social order, and the conditions for strong and lasting imperial rule. I  will also identify potential sources and explore how Shāh Walī Allāh’s  theory relates to previous Islamic accounts of social origination—particularly the akhlāq tradition as represented by Ṭūsī and Dawwānī—as well as Indo-Islamic political literature, notablyBaranī’s, Abū’l-Faẓl’s,  and Najm-i Sānī’s works.9 In the second part of the article I engage in a  detailed analysis of Shāh Walī Allāh’s views on the decline of the state  and empire/caliphate and investigate how they relate to the political  and social realities that prevailed in late Mughal India.

In the concluding section, I suggest ways in which the findings of  this article might be of more than historical relevance for the study of  Shāh Walī Allāh’s political thought. I specifically examine how Shāh Walī Allāh uses the examples of the Sassanians and Byzantine empires  as heuristic devices to illustrate the process of decay of Mughal power.  I also point to parallels between Shāh Walī Allāh’s ideas on the economic dimensions of imperial decay and the ways in which Byzantine  statesmen and literati theorized remedies for the weaknesses of Byzan tine society in the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries.

I. The Rise of the State

The Origins of Social Life

The pivot point of Shāh Walī Allāh’s social theory is the concept of  irtifāq. The term bears connotations that cannot be adequately ren dered by any single English term, but it generally refers to various stages  in the process of social genesis.10 In the first irtifāq, people engage in  tillage, create languages, learn how to cook food, and a man chooses  one woman as his partner. The second irtifāq witnesses the emergence  and evolution of sciences acquired through experience, elegance, deli cate living, and comprehensive view (al-ra’y al-kullī).

Shāh Walī Allāh names five  types  of wisdom:  (1) the wisdom of  living (al-ḥikmah al-ma‘ashiyah), which deals with human conduct and  practical knowledge about eating, drinking, dressing, and so forth;  (2) the wisdom of domestic life (al-ḥikmah al-manziliyah), which concerns the organization of the household; (3) the wisdom of earning a  livelihood (al-ḥikmah al-iktisabiyah), which refers to functional special ization and the various crafts and professions which people practice  according to their skills; (4) the wisdom of mutual dealings (al-ḥikmah  al-ta‘amuliyah), which pertains to commercial operations (mu‘āmalāt);  and (5) the wisdom of cooperation (al-ḥikmah al-ta‘awuniyah), which  deals with partnership and commercial enterprises.11 But social evils  such as avarice and envy soon creep in, giving rise to social tensions  and disputes, and some men seek to overpower others or are naturally  inclined to plunder and kill. Hence, the members of the community  feel compelled to appoint a ruler, who possesses abundant resources and  is able to attract wise men from other countries, to correct and punish  evildoers and collect taxes. In the fourth irtifāq a caliph is appointed to  merge together and rule over preexisting states and kingdoms.12

All men need food, drink, and shelter. In Shāh Walī Allāh’s view,  every species has a law implanted into the breasts of its individuals, and  all creatures strive to meet their needs. But man has three capacities  that are not found in other animals. First, he possesses a comprehensive  view: while animals are directed to an objective perceived through the  senses or to an imagined objective driven by their physical needs such  as hunger, thirst, and lust, man is uniquely endowed with the ability to  perceive and strive after a rational benefit that has no motivation in his  physical nature. This prompts human beings to establish a social order,  perfect their character, and seek mutual affection. Second, while ani mals desire things such as food to fulfill their needs and protect them selves against the cold, man has been equipped with aesthetic sensibil ity (zarāfah). He thus tries to move beyond the level of bare necessity  and aspires to aesthetic and emotional delight and elegance, a beautiful  partner, delicious food, good clothing, and a comfortable house. Third,  man is characterized by takāmul, that is, an inner drive toward self perfection. Men of intelligence discover and develop the appropriate  supports of civilization, look for water resources or dig wells and store  water, learn which seeds are edible and figure out how to cook or store  them; those who are unable to discover those supports on their own  perceive their utility and follow what the “wise” propose to them.13 Shāh  Walī  Allāh  comes  very  close  to  Montesquieu  when  he  acknowledges that differences in temperaments and social mores exist  among various peoples and explains that the three capabilities unique  to men are not found in equal measure in all nations. On one level,  he explains, are primitive societies such as the Bedouins, who live on  mountain peaks and in regions far from sound climates. On another,  higher level are settled populations and the urban centers of healthful  regions that are inhabited by people endowed by nature with superior  virtues and produce wise men.14

The Emergence and Evolution of Human Civilization

Science takes root during the second irtifāq, as men explore ways to go  beyond the mere satisfaction of needs. It specifically examines and tests  developments of the first irtifāq and lays down criteria for the selec tion of attitudes that bring benefit. People with the best temperaments  are predisposed toward superior virtues, and they communicate these   virtues and morals to one another through social interaction. The  refinement of morals concerns the proper manner of drinking, walk ing, sitting, and clothing, and every nation develops a style and set of   manners and habits according to its own temperament and habits.15 Language serves as a means of expressing and designating acts,  attitudes, and bodily movements associated with a particular sound  through onomatopoeia and causal connection. Sounds are imitated  and then used to derive forms that correspond to various meanings.  Arts and crafts follow, such as agriculture, digging wells, cooking, mak ing pots, domesticating and taming animals, creating shelter from heat  and cold in caves and huts, and producing clothing from animal skins  or trees.16 A male is guided to select a mate and not share her with  anyone else in order to alleviate his lust, perpetuate his lineage, and  receive assistance in domestic needs and in raising and educating chil dren. He is also guided to create tools for cultivating, planting, digging  wells, and domesticating animals, and soon the exchange of goods and  cooperation take place. The wisest and strongest men subjugate others  and become leaders, and people need to devise methods for settling  quarrels and disputes, restraining malefactors, and repelling external  enemies. The members of every nation contribute differently to the  evolution of civilization: one might love beauty and luxury; another  might excel in such qualities as courage, magnanimity, eloquence, or  intelligence; and others might aspire to fame or higher ranks.17

The second phase of social development signals the emergence of  the art of economic transactions, that is, the science that concerns  the exchange of products, cooperation, and the means of earning. As  people become more refined and seek pleasures and luxury, the crafts  and professions expand and become more diverse. Every man pursues  a single occupation that suits his natural disposition and skills.18 For  example, a courageous person enters the military and an intelligent  man with a good memory goes into accounting. Sometimes coincidence plays a role, as when a son or neighbor of a smith finds the art  of smithing easier or when a person who lives by the sea practices the  art of fishing. However, some people lead parasitic lives or engage in  activities harmful to society, such as robbery, gambling, and begging.19

Men exchange property for property or property for usufruct, that is,  hire and lease. Goodwill and mutual affection among the members of  society are essential conditions for domestic stability and prosperity.  They develop practices for contracts and conventions and establish  guidelines for share-cropping, partnerships, and hire and lease. They  also lay down rules for borrowing and entrusting money and redressing financial fraud; subsequently, witnessing, the composition of legal  documents, and mortgages take place and a monetary system comes  into being.20

The second irtifāq gives rise to division of labor and aesthetics  as well. People agree among themselves that each one will pursue a  distinct occupation and will attain expertise in the use of its tools.  When many people simultaneously desire the same object, it becomes  necessary to develop conventions for commissioning and paying for  goods, and gold and silver are used as means of exchange because of  their small size, portability, homogeneity, and suitability to adorn the  human body and be used as currency. Following the emergence of the  main occupations—that is, agriculture, herding, and distribution of  products, and crafts, such as carpentry, iron smithing, and weavingtrade evolved into distinct professions, as did the administration of the  affairs of the city.21

Shāh Walī Allāh’s discussion of  the  third irtifāq—that is, the sci ence that investigates ways to preserve and strengthen the bonds  among the inhabitants of the city—is his longest. Pursuant to his  notion that human society arises from the aggregation of persons who  live in proximity to one another and engage in mutual collaboration although they dwell in separate houses, Shāh Walī Allāh conceives of  the state as a single individual composed of distinct parts that share a  common attitude and work together toward a common purpose. But as  the equivalent of a living organism, human society also suffers from dis orders, disturbances, and illnesses. Shāh Walī Allāh sees strife and con flict as endemic to social life: because human society comprises a large  number of individuals, agreement on how to maintain the just practice  is elusive. Moreover, it is difficult for one man to rebuke others unless  he is distinguished by rank; anything else risks infighting and killing.  Thus, the majority of influential people agree to obey a person who has  his own circle of supporters and enough force to contain disorder and  punish those who are greedy, violent, or prone to anger and killing.22

The Ideal Ruler

Shāh Walī Allāh elaborates on  the practicalities of government,  the  qualities required in the paradigmatic ruler, and the relations between  the sovereign and his subjects, staff, and subordinate officials. A ruler  who lacks courage, valor, and fortitude in combat and prowess to confront those who attempt to subvert his rule will incur the contempt of  his subjects. At the same time, if he is not forbearing and lenient, he  will crush them through his strength, and if he lacks wisdom, he will  be unable to discover the best ways to administer the affairs of the city.  The ruler should be in full possession of his mental faculties, of mature  age, free, and male, and have the senses of sight, hearing, and speech  intact. People must agree on his nobility and that of his ancestors; he  should display praiseworthy skills and must convince the people that  he will not spare any effort to uphold order in his realm.23

Shāh Walī Allāh devotes particular attention to the skill sets nec essary for a ruler to gain the confidence of his people. The exemplary  ruler is expected to epitomize superior leadership virtues such as cour age, wisdom, generosity, forgiveness for malefactors and evildoers, and  should be driven by the desire to promote the public welfare. He should  also have a keen insight into human nature, exhibit sagacity and the  ability to discern the secrets in men’s hearts, and refrain from procras tinating, especially if he detects animosity toward himself or attempts  to undermine his position and erode his power. To illustrate how the  sovereign ought to deal with his subjects, Shāh Walī Allāh employs the  metaphor of the hunter who studies a gazelle in the forest and deliber ates on the best strategy, remaining in his position and lying in wait  until he sees that his quarry is not paying attention, at which moment  he quietly crawls toward it or tries to lure it with music and throw it  a fine decoy. Similarly, the ruler ought to cultivate bonds of love with  the people and display the attitude that people like in clothing, speech,  and manners. He should approach them humbly, offer them advice,  and show affection in a way that is not frivolous. But until he feels that  they are convinced of his superiority and preeminence and commands  their loyalty and respect, he must constantly remind them that no one  is equal to him. Then he should strive to keep them in this condition  and grant them favors.24

Shāh Walī Allāh also discusses how the sovereign should deal with  animosity and threats to his rule. He should compel obedience and  punish the unruly. He should also raise the rank or increase the salary  of those who excel in war or in the collection of taxes or management  and shun and reprimand those who display treachery, opposition, or  disobedience by reducing their salaries and demoting them. Although  the ruler is entitled to lead a more comfortable or luxurious life than  the people, he should not assign them too difficult tasks, such as cultivating wasteland or guarding a remote district. He should not hesitate  to punish malefactors, but only after there is sound evidence adduced  by officials and for the sake of the common good.25

A substantial part of Shāh Walī Allāh’s treatment of the principles  of effective leadership is devoted to the criteria for the selection of the  various officials: the ruler needs people to assist him in fulfilling his  tasks and administering financial resources to sustain the military and  remunerate his aides.26 Able and loyal administrators protect the ruler  from evil just as the hands carry weapons and protect the entire body.  They also proffer advice to the ruler just like the mind and the senses  provide information to the human organism. The ruler’s ministers must  be trustworthy, carry out orders, and bear goodwill both in private and  in public. The ruler must be quick to dismiss any official who strays  from these principles.27

Shāh Walī Allāh enumerates five  principal aides and court func tionaries: (1) the judge (qāḍī); (2) the commander of the armed forces  (‘amīr) in charge of selecting and training soldiers, deploying spies, and  gathering intelligence about the plans of potential enemies; (3) the  governor of the city (sā‘īs), who is in charge of appointing a leader  for each group; (4) the revenue collector (‘āmil); and (5) the minister  (wakīl), whose function is to administer the income and expenditure  and minister to the ruler’s daily needs.28 In the al-Budūr al-Bāzighah, Shāh Walī Allāh provides an expanded list that includes another two  offices: (1) the head of religious affairs (shaikh-ul Islām) in charge of  propagating religion and providing spiritual guidance, and (2) the sage  (ḥakīm) who possesses expertise on medicine, poetry, astrology, history,  mathematics, and letter writing.29

The ruler should have the ability to distinguish between those who  pretend to love him out of fear or greed and those who genuinely sup port his rule. He should also be able to discern each person’s merits,  monitor the conduct and activities of the state officials, and keep  abreast of new developments. He must select a number of assistants  proportionate to the needs and the size of the state and must deter mine their salaries. Shāh Walī Allāh recommends that the ruler adopt  a just system of collecting land taxes without burdening the people;  taxes should be levied on those who possess large property and wealth  derived from husbandry, agriculture, and commercial pursuits.30 In his exposition of the modes conducive to stable and lasting rule,  Shāh Walī Allāh devotes special attention to the ruler’s relationship  with the military, using the analogy of a skilled and experienced rid ing master who knows all of his horse’s gaits and bad habits, and the  best way to train it: the trainer closely observes the horse and, when  it displeases him or disobeys his orders, he tames its impetuousness  in a way consistent with the horse’s nature. He does not aim to per plex the horse’s mind, for the horse cannot understand the trainer’s  motives; instead, he seeks to engrave the image of what he teaches  in the mind and heart of the horse. Once he has made sure that the  horse will perform the right acts and refrain from reprehensible ones,  the trainer continues his training until he is sure that the desired  mode of behavior is habitual for the horse, so that even without his  whips the horse will desist from actions that do not conform to the  desired goal. Likewise, the ruler as the trainer of the military must  know the best methods for taking action and for using the things that  will serve as a warning to them.31

The Caliphate

The fourth irtifāq signals the apex of political organization. In each  city a ruler is appointed, courageous persons gather around him,  and wealth is collected in the form of taxes. The differences in the  temperaments and abilities of the kings elicit friction: certain rulers  attempt to conquer another’s territory or fight one another for unimportant reasons, such as desire for wealth or land or due to envy, greed,  resentment, and malice. Thus, the kings were compelled to appoint a  caliph or to obey a single ruler who has the authority of the caliph ate (khilāfah). The true caliph holds undisputed sway over his realm  and possesses so much military might and equipment that it is almost  impossible for another person to challenge him. Just as the head of the  state soothes or remedies social tensions, the fourth irtifāq is the sci ence that examines the policies of the cities and their rulers and the  means whereby collaboration among people of various regions can be  fostered. And just as political authority within the first political com munities originates in a primordial compact the caliph is appointed  upon the consent of the rulers of existing states. The caliph must be  on guard against all factors that can jeopardize his authority: emergen cies, natural calamities, disarray and factious commotion, the expen diture of large amounts of money, and wicked individuals who plunder  the property of the people, incarcerate their sons, and dishonor their  wives.32

One of Shāh Walī Allāh’s novelties is that he offers one of the most  analytically refined accounts of the origin, nature, and function of the  caliphate. Shāh Walī Allāh goes beyond previous Islamic writers such  as al-Fārābī, who envisage the caliphate as the pinnacle of a constant  process of associational evolution starting from the creation of simple types of political organization.33 As al-Fārābī puts it, the increase  of human needs leads to more complex forms of social organization  and culminates in the creation of a universal state encompassing all  existing nations. In order to secure the means for his subsistence, man  by nature needs various things that he cannot acquire by himself, so  he relies on mutual aid and is compelled to live in association with  others. The increase of men results in the formation of communities,  some of which are perfect, some of which are imperfect. The imperfect  types include the union of people in a village, a quarter, a street, or in  a house. The perfect types can be classified into small, medium, and  great: the small one is the union of the inhabitants of the city in the  territory of any nation, the middle one results from the formation of  one nation in a certain region, and the great one signals the union of  all the communities of the inhabited world.34 Just as people living in a  city strive for those things that allow them to attain ultimate perfection  through mutual collaboration, the excellent nation is one in which  all of its cities aspire to felicity. Accordingly, the excellent universal  state can come into being when all the nations that compose it work  together to reach felicity.35

Shāh Walī Allāh provides a more detailed distinction among three  types of caliphate:36 caliphate in a special sense (khilāfat-i khāṣṣa); caliphate in the general sense (khilāfat-i ‘āmma); and tyrannical caliph ate (khilāfat-i jābira).37 When humankind was in a state of sin and anar chy, God sent the Prophet Muḥammad for its guidance, and the func tion of the first four special caliphs was to complete the mission of  the Prophet. The general caliphate is a human-made institution that  emanates from human agreement and the opinion or judgment (rā’y) of a particular group of men. The caliph in the general sense, then, is  an ordinary human being and as such he is susceptible to human weak nesses; therefore his rule can easily slide into tyranny. As I will discuss  later, Shāh Walī Allāh refers to the Sassanian and Byzantine empires  as exempla of the caliphate in the general sense. The tyrannical caliph ate comes into being when the caliph breaks his obligation to enforce  religious precepts and fails to wage jihād and apply the sharī‘a or, when  he applies Islamic law, does so erroneously.

The caliph ought to determine the purpose of war, suppress inter state conflict, restrain malefactors, repel enemies, and crush those  who ignite seditious activities by intimidating them, assassinating or  arresting their leaders, or seizing their property. But at the same time,  Shāh Walī  Allāh  cautions  against  the  caliph’s  setting  goals  beyond  his capacity and resources or seeking to acquire wealth by murdering  his supporters. The caliph should try to gain support from resourceful  people and the notables. In war, he should inspire awe in his enemies  and attempt to erode their power. In case he suspects that his former  enemies engage in intrigues, he should levy heavy land and poll taxes,  destroy their strongholds, and take all possible measures to neutralize  their power.38

Medieval and Early Modern Islamic Sources 

on the Emergence of Social Life

It will be instructive here to briefly explore Islamic accounts of the  origins of social life and identify possible sources of Shāh Walī Allāh’s  thought. One  such  source might be Nasīr al-Dīn Ṭūsī’s (1201–1274)  Akhlāq-i Nāṣirī (The Nasirean Ethics), an ethical-political treatise that  had an enduring influence on Syriac, Persian, and Indo-Islamic political writing. Affinities to Shāh Walī Allāh’s ideas may also be found in  the writings of Dawwānī, especially in his Jalalian Ethics, as well as in  Abū’l-Faẓl’s Institutes of Akbar and Najm-i Sānī’s Admonition of Jahāngīr.

Ṭūsī operates on the Aristotelian idea that humans are political by  nature39 but also stresses that they need crafts to meet their needs. He  reckons that divine wisdom has ordained disparity in the aspirations  and opinions of the members of society and that each person is inclined  to a different occupation. The diversity of the aptitudes and interests of  the members of human society generates internal disorder and division.  Since mutual aid depends on a diversity of crafts, which results from  the diversity of ends, the perpetuation of social life is contingent on the  existence of a set of rules and a ruler in charge of enforcing justice and  suppressing internecine strife.40

In keeping with his idea that man is by nature formed to live in a  society, Ṭūsī holds that man by nature needs a “civilized life.” But the  motives and ends of human actions differ. So, if men are left to their  own natures, no cooperation can result, because the powerful will seek  to exploit and oppress the others and the greedy will covet the property  of the others. As soon as strife sets in, men engage in mutual destruction and injury. Ṭūsī infers from this that government is a  certain type  of management that is required to render what is deserved to each   individual, to restrain each individual from encroaching upon the  rights or disturbing the function of the others, and to ensure that each  member of the society carries through the specific duty at which he is  adept by nature.41

Ṭūsī’s  narrative  of  social  genesis  was  reproduced  in  Muḥammad  Dawwānī’s  (1426/7–1512/3) Akhlāq-i Jalālī (The Jalalian Ethics), a  revised and expanded version of the Nasirean Ethics that enjoyed wide  dissemination in the Mughal world.42 Like Ṭūsī, Dawwānī holds that  humankind’s sustenance depends on food, clothing, shelter, arms, and  the ability and methods to acquire the tools essential to the crafts, such  as carpentry and blacksmithing. Men need to live together in such a  way that each individual pursues a distinct task and engages in cooperation with others so as to obtain all things necessary to sustain life.43 Dawwānī restates Ṭūsī’s doctrine that man is by nature inclined to  civilization, which is derived from the term “city” (madīnah).44 At the  same time, however, he warns of the danger of social havoc and disrup tion, should a central authority within human society cease to exist.  Dawwānī’s justification of political authority rests on the idea of dispar ity in the dispositions and claims of the members of human society. Men  cannot be left to their own natures, because each one of them would  pursue his own interest and would cause injuries to the other. Hence,  some provision must be made for rendering all individuals content with  their rightful portion and restraining them from causing mutual harm.  This provision is a government, and to this end there must be rules, an  executive, and a currency.45 The ruler is a person endowed with divine support in order to satisfy the interests of the various segments of the  body politic and uphold domestic stability and order.46 Ṭūsī’s and Dawwānī’s  views  on  social genesis had a  distinguished  Nachleben in the Indo-Islamic context and penetrated Mughal politi cal discourse through the circulation of copies of the Jalalian Ethics by  former students of Dawwānī in the Deccan and Gujarat.47 Similar ideas  occur in the Ā’īn-i Akbarī (The Institutes of Akbar), written by Abū’l Faẓl ‘Allāmī  (1551–1602), the famous vizier of the Mughal emperor  Akbar (1542–1605; r. 1556–1605). By Abū’l-Faẓl’s time the influence  of the old Aristotelian doctrine about human sociability seems to have  withered away: in his exposition of the genesis of social life, Abū’l-Faẓl  builds on the akhlāq tradition48 but dispenses with the standard formula  that man is by nature a gregarious creature destined to live in asso ciation with others. He highlights instead the diversity characterizing  human nature and sets forth the vision of the state as consisting of het erogeneous parts. These considerations form the basis for Abū’l-Faẓl’s  vindication of kingship as the guarantee of social stability: pād stands  for stability and shāh indicates that the ruler is the source of stability.  The absence of authority gives rise to strife and selfish ambitions, caus ing humankind to lapse into a state of anarchy and lust. By the light of  imperial justice, Abū’l-Faẓl argues, some men follow with cheerfulness  the path of obedience, whereas others abstain from violence through  fear of punishment.49

Shāh  Walī  Allāh’s  more  immediate  precursor  was  Muḥammad  Bāqir Najm-i Sānī (d. 1637), who served as governor in various parts  of the Mughal Empire under Jahāngīr (1569–1627, r. 1605–1627) and  Shah  Jahān (1592–1666, r. 1628–1658). According  to Najm-i Sānī’s  Mau‘iẓah-i Jahāngīrī (Admonition of  Jahāngīr or Advice on [the Art]  of Rulership, 1612/13), the defining characteristics of royal rule are  exalted rank and high station. Unless the ruler regulates the affairs of  the people and acts as the refuge of the vulnerable members of human  society, clandestine rebels and insurgents, who are driven by tyrannical  feelings and engage in contumacious and aberrant conduct, will seek to  disturb the nobility and the common people.50

A  salient  theme  in  Shāh Walī  Allāh’s  theory  of  the  state  is  the  variety of ways whereby domestic balance can be maintained and har monious interaction among various social groups can be ensured. Shāh  Walī Allāh evokes the “circle of justice” formula in medieval Islamic  political literature. And these ideas are rooted even further back in  history, in the works of ancient political thinkers, such as Plato, and  Iranian ideals of rulership.

According  to Shāh Walī Allāh,  the  various  parts  of  the  state are  interrelated; the preservation of balance and harmony is like salt sea soning food.51 The third irtifāq necessitates the appointment of a ruler  in charge of maintaining social balance and domestic tranquillity; with  the multiplication of cities and states, in the fourth irtifāq a caliph is  appointed to erase interstate conflicts.52 Shāh Walī Allāh is particularly  emphatic about the caliph’s function in maintaining balance among  opposing and conflicting elements and purging the body politic of  excesses. The ideal caliph ought to be on his guard against revolution ary activities and subversive tendencies, must create an extensive net work of spies and informers, and must effectively employ perspicacity  about human character. As soon as he sees a faction forming among his  men, he should swiftly form another group and ensure that it will not  connive with the rebels. It is vital that this new group obey the caliph’s  commands, show goodwill toward him, and pray for him, acclaiming  his glory in large assemblies and on coins bearing his name.53

The ruler’s duty to uphold the delicate equilibrium among the vari ous segments of the body politic is compared in medieval Islamic writ ing to the physician’s function in maintaining the equilibrium (i‘tidāl) in the human body.54 Moderation is important both as a means for  moral perfection but also in the context of the ruler’s role as the healer  of the social organism who, like a skilled physician, diagnoses diseases  and applies remedies.55 As Shāh Walī Allāh phrases it, the city is not  merely the presence of walls, markets, and high buildings but constitutes a bond among the various orders of human society. In the progress  of civilization, different groups engage in mutual dealings and become  woven together like a single body. Shāh Walī Allāh deduces from this  the need for a physician (i.e., ruler) to preserve the healthy condition  of the city and to treat maladies. By the same token, on a transnational  level, the caliph is the physician of states that suffer from corruption  and factional discord.56

Shāh Walī Allāh here stands in a philosophical tradition that can  be traced back to the “circle of justice” concept in medieval Islamic  political writing. The “circle of justice” or “circle of power” maxim57 has its  roots in  two popular dicta imputed  to Aristotle and Ardashīr,  king of Persia (r. 224–241 c.e.) and founder of the Sassanid dynasty.58 In the saying ascribed to Aristotle, the world is parallel to a large gar den which is administered by the state; the state signifies authority  founded on the law; the law is a way of ruling applied by the king,  who acts like a shepherd; the king is supported by the army, the suste nance of which depends on tax revenues; tax revenues are sustenance  procured by the subjects; the subjects are slaves procured by justice,  which is the element that guarantees the proper function of the world.  Ardashīr is reported to have said that government is contingent on the  existence of men, men in their turn need money, money comes from  cultivation of the land, and cultivation can take place only if there is  justice and salutary rule.59 The “circle of justice” concept assumes that  the ideal social organization can be achieved by ensuring that each part  of society confines itself to its allocated duties and does not encroach  upon the functions of the others. Integral to the “circle of justice” is  the notion that the state encompasses diverse functional groupings  with competing interests. The satisfaction of these varied desires and  interests is seen as a prerequisite to social stability, and often the various social groups are perceived as analogous to the four elements and  humors of the natural body.

The “circle of justice” had a pervasive influence on the akhlāq and  Indo-Islamic  political writing. Ṭūsī, in  the Nasirean Ethics, takes his  cue from the old Irano-Islamic division of social groups and sets forth  a scheme of social organization based on four main parts: (1) men of  the pen, such as the masters of the sciences, jurists, judges, secretaries, accountants, geometers, astronomers, physicians, and poets, who  correspond to water; (2) men of the sword, that is, soldiers, who are  the counterpart of fire; (3) men of transactions, merchants, masters of  crafts and professions, and tax collectors, who are like air; and (4) farmers, who correspond to earth. Ṭūsī describes the ruler’s principal func tion as upholding the balance among these groups, just as a balanced  temperament  depends  on  the  equilibrium  of  the four  elements. Ṭūsī  also points out that just as the domination of one element over the  others is likely to upset the equilibrium of the human body, in similar  fashion the predominance of one segment over the rest would upset the  equilibrium of the body politic.60

In his Jalalian Ethics,  Dawwānī follows Ṭūsī  and  proposes  a four fold division of the populace into: (1) men of knowledge—theologians,  jurists, secretaries, fiscal officials, geometry experts, astronomers, phy sicians, and poets, whose task is to perform religious duties; (2) war riors; (3) merchants, artisans, and craftsmen, who procure the needs of  life; and (4) farmers, who produce food.61 Like Ṭūsī, Dawwānī points  to the detrimental effects of the domination of one of these groups  over the others. As long as every class retains its proper place, carries  out the specific tasks assigned to it, and receives the merits and rank  due to it, the temperament of the social organism remains in a state  of equilibrium. But as soon as one passes beyond its proper measure,  domestic balance is disturbed, leading eventually to the disintegration  of the state.62 Just as the equipoise of bodily temperament depends on  the proper mixture of the four elements, the equipoise of a well-formed  body politic is contingent on the balance among the four classes.63 And  just as a physician must be acquainted with the causes of disease and  their proper treatment and must seek to preserve the equilibrium of the  human temperament, one of the first duties of the king as the world’s  physician is to know the reasons and remedies for the political and  social maladies and emergencies or misfortunes that might befall his  domain.64

The impact of the “circle of justice” is discernible in the politi cal  literature  of  the  Delhi  Sultanate  period  too.  Baranī  proposes  in  his Fatāwa-i Jahāndārī (Precepts on [World] Rulership) a social divi sion among farmers, traders, soldiers, and government officials. Baranī  advocates the strict regimentation of the populace and warns of the  potential hazards deriving from mobility among the various social  groupings. A prime condition for  the  stability of  the  state for Baranī  is that each person confines himself to his assigned profession. Baranī,  like Shāh Walī Allāh, emphasizes the economic factors that account  for the devolution of the state. He specifically advocates low prices so  that each occupational group can devote itself to its prescribed tasks.  He also maintains that high prices can create social chaos because they  compel people to abandon their own profession and station, leading  soldiers to turn to agriculture, farmers to take up trade activities, traders  to aspire to high offices, shopkeepers to try to become officers, men of  noble birth to become merchants, and merchants to seek government  and army posts.65

In like manner, Abū’l-Faẓl reckons division of labor to be the hall mark of a well-ordered society and defines the principal duty of the  ruler as entrusting the citizens with specific functions and monitoring  the operation of the segments of the body politic. The ruler should put  each of these in its proper place. Drawing on the “circle of justice,”  Abū’l-Faẓl outlines a scheme of four occupational classes that corre spond to the four elements: (1) warriors, who represent the element of  fire and combat rebellions and strife; (2) artisans and merchants, who  may be compared to air; (3) the learned—philosophers, physicians,  scholars of arithmetic, geometricians, and astronomers—who resemble  water; and (4) farmers and laborers, who are the equivalent of earth.66

II. The Decline of States and Empires

The Disorders of the State

Shāh Walī Allāh  does not confine himself  to mapping  out  the  vari ous developmental stages of civilization; he also offers an extensive  account of emergencies:

a. A number of wicked individuals who possess power form a group and  pursue their interests; they subvert just practice either out of desire to  usurp the wealth of others or to harm others out of hostility, malice, or  the desire to dominate.

b. An offender injures another person or abuses his family by molesting  his wife, daughters, or sisters or tries to tamper with his property by  violence or secret theft; or one person impugns the honor of another  person by slandering or offending him.

c. Persons engage in activities that disrupt social order, such as using  black magic or poisons, spreading evil habits, fomenting dissent and  discontent, or encouraging people to challenge the ruler, servants to  plot against their masters, and wives against their husbands.

d. The propagation of noxious habits, such as homosexuality and bestial ity, and modes of conduct that can give rise to disputes and friction,  such as a number of men desiring the same woman or addiction to  wine. This results in disregard for the necessary supports of civilization.

e. Persons engage in transactions harmful to the city, such as gambling,  lending at interest, bribery, cheating in the sale of commodities, high  prices, and hoarding commodities.

f. People get embroiled in controversies and vacillate between different  positions as long as the situation has not been clarified.

g. The community reverts into nomadic life or a condition similar to the  first irtifāq, when people migrate to other cities or engage in activities  harmful to the city, as is the case when most people turn to trade or  make their living through warfare and agriculture declines.

h. The stampede of wild animals and the spread of vermin.67

In addition to proposing special measures for each of the emergen cies mentioned above, Shāh Walī Allāh recommends a series of general  measures intended to enhance the defense of the state. For example, he  counsels the construction of walls, forts, and bridges; the appointment  of border garrisons; and the creation of markets. He also recommends  securing water supplies, discovering water springs, building wells, and  facilitating the transportation of merchandise through the construc tion  of  docks  at  the  shores  of  rivers.  Shāh Walī Allāh’s  program for  dealing with extraordinary circumstances is not confined to prescrip tions of practical nature but extends to the moral aspects of domestic  unity and the modes of interaction between the ruler and his subjects.  The sovereign should cultivate bonds of friendship among the people  and interact in a friendly manner with merchants and foreigners; this  will prompt them to visit his realm more often. He should also make  sure that farmers do not leave the land uncultivated and should offer  incentives for artisans to improve their work. Finally, the ruler should  encourage the people to acquire skills such as calligraphy, arithmetic,  history, medicine, and methods of advancing knowledge. Protective  measures include being able to distinguish immoral from moral habits,  identify which citizens are in need of support, and employ the best  craftsmen.68

Imperial Decline

Shāh  Walī  Allāh’s  theory  about  the  caliphate  in  the  general  sense  revolves around the two major factors which, in his view, account for  imperial decline in his own day: (1) the depletion of the public trea sury, and (2) parasitism, or the fact that many people seek to secure  income by serving as soldiers or by becoming ‘ulamā’ (religious schol ars), ascetics, and poets and by receiving gifts from the rulers. The lat ter causes heavy taxation on farmers and traders, then the constant  increase of taxes leads to the ruin of the productive classes and incites  those who survive to stand up against taxation and rebel against the  government.69

In his private writings and letters, Shāh Walī Allāh berates the fact  that wealth came to be concentrated in the hands of Hindus.70 But,  more importantly, he construes the malfunction of the Mughal govern ment as a sign of moral decadence and overall failure to implement the  teachings of Islam. In an eleventh-hour attempt to save the Mughal  state from ultimate downfall, Shāh Walī Allāh called on the Afghan  ruler Aḥmad Shāh Abdālī (d. 1772) to invade India. He offers fulsome  praise of the Afghan warlord for his bravery and foresight and urges  him to launch a full-scale operation against the Marathas and Jats and  to wipe out polytheistic practices.71

Shāh  Walī  Allāh’s  epistles  on  Mughal  political  disintegration  should be read against the background of a series of events that led to  the gradual decay of Mughal rule:72 the incursions by Maratha, Jat, and  Sikh forces;73 the invasion of the army of the Iranian ruler Nādir Shāh  (1688–1747, r. 1736–1747) in 1739, which struck a blow to the stature  of the emperor and strained the Empire economically and militarily; a  devastating military debacle of the Mughal forces at the battle of Karnal on 24 February 1739 and the massive slaughter of residents of Delhi  perpetrated by soldiers that gave rise to popular resentment; and the  constant plots and intrigues of the nobles and courtiers. The situation  came to a head when, after the death of the Mughal ruler Muḥammad  Shāh (d. 1748), his son and successor Aḥmad Shāh Bahādur (1725– 1775, r. 1748–1754) became a pliant tool in the hands of influential  ministers and nobles, which rendered the Empire’s capital vulnerable  to assaults by rebels.

Shāh Walī Allāh reproves the imperial administration for its inabil ity to suppress sedition. He points to the Jats’ taking over Gujarat and  Malwa; the rulers’ luxurious way of life, profligate spending, and self aggrandizement; the irregular and disrupted flow of revenues from the  provinces; the corruption of local governors and tax agents in the col lection and administration of revenue; and the oppression of the lower  social strata of the population. In addition to the letters which he sent  to Aḥmad Shāh Abdālī, Shāh Walī Allāh made a direct appeal to the  emperor and the nobles and spelled out an elaborate program intended  to ensure the stability and continued existence of the Empire:74

a. He cautions against the policy of appointing a large number of jagirs (fief lords) who end up shirking their duties to the army and rent out  their lands. He recommends assigning large pieces of land to nobles  and reintroducing Shāh Jahān’s practice of paying the lower members  of the nobility in cash.

b. He impresses upon the government the need to ensure that soldiers  receive a regular salary, because delays in paying salaries compels sol diers to rely on loans at high rates of interest and neglect their duties.

c. He exhorts the emperor to expand the state property (khāliṣa) to the  region surrounding Delhi, Hisar, and Sirhind.

d. He suggests that the central administration reassert its authority and  regain its capacity to gather revenues.

e. He urges the emperor and nobles to give up their extravagant and  luxurious way of life. 

Shāh Walī Allāh stands forth as an intimate observer of the politi cal events of his time.75 His interest in Mughal politics can partly be  explained by his affiliation with the Naqhsbandi order.76 The order  advocated the active involvement of leading Sufi figures in politics,  with the aim to influence the policies and decisions of rulers and  thereby affect the lives of Muslims.77 In the context of the central  820 journal of world history, december 2012 and eastern Islamic empires, rulers often had to muster the support of  the order to legitimize and consolidate their rule and secure popular  support.78

Shāh Walī Allāh on Byzantine Decline

What gives particular poignancy to Shāh Walī Allāh’s theorizing about  imperial decline is his use of the Persian and Byzantine paradigms as a  heuristic device to trace the root causes of the decay of Mughal power.  Shāh  Walī  Allāh  castigates  the  Sassanian  (‘ajam)79 and Byzantine  (rūm) empires, noting that their failure to collect sufficient revenues  and build up necessary defenses was the principal factor that led to  their collapse. Their rulers had passed on hereditary kingship for many  generations and had become so engrossed in the pleasures of this world  that they neglected the next world. They became deeply immersed  in comforts and derived pride from possessing them; in fact, scholars  came from far lands to learn the arts associated with fine living. The  Persians and Byzantines pursued life’s pleasures with increasing enthusiasm; their rulers competed and showed off to one another until they  used to rebuke those rulers who did not wear beautiful clothes or who  wore a girdle or crown whose value was less than a hundred thousand  dirhems or who did not reside in a lofty palace that included bathtubs,  bathing pools, gardens, swift riding animals, and handsome servitors,  or those who were not generous in distributing food. This emphasis  on luxury and pleasure penetrated their lives to such an extent that  it was like an incurable disease that caused their markets and cities to  perish.80

Luxurious living papered over mounting expenditures, and to make  up for draining the state budget, rulers imposed exorbitant taxation  on the peasantry and traders and oppressed them to the point that if  they refused to pay taxes they were subjected to torture, and if they  obeyed they became like donkeys and cattle, which are used for farming according to their master’s needs and whims. Consequently, greed  and luxury set in, and the people were so desperate in such a state of  depredation and misery that they totally neglected religion; they were  concerned solely with material comforts, and they abandoned the prin

ciples of the professions upon which the order of the world is based.  Some people ingratiated themselves with the rulers; others emulated  the habits of their leaders but did not perform what was necessary and  tried instead to merely subsist; still others engaged in parasitic activities  by becoming poets, ascetics, and Sufis, relying on gifts and financial  aid from the emperors; and some of these groups ended up oppressing  and exploiting others and sought to make their living by befriending or  flattering the rulers.81

Shāh  Walī  Allāh’s  statements  on  Byzantine  decline  point  to  a  major lacuna in scholarship. Previous studies rarely address medieval  and early modern Islamic views of the political organization of the   Byzantine Empire and the ways in which Byzantine historiography and  political writing perceived the rise of Mongol rule and the spread of  Islam in central and south Asia.82 Medieval Islamic literature is characterized by the tendency to refer to political leaders and methods of  government before the advent of Islam or in non-Muslim lands in the  context of discussions on the conditions for salutary rule according to  the tenets of Islam. The earliest references to pre-Islamic rulers occur  in the Qu’rān, in which the term malik (king)83 is applied to the pha raohs of ancient Egypt to signify unrighteous political conduct and  arbitrary and unjust rule,84 although later Arab authors took a more  favorable stance toward ancient Egyptian kingship and commended  the pharaohs for such virtues as generosity, piety, and dedication to the  welfare of their subjects.85

One of the first references to Byzantium (al-rūm) appears in the  Qur’ān in the context of the Byzantine-Sassanid war at the beginning  of the seventh century.86 Just like Shāh Walī Allāh, a number of Arab  writers saw Byzantine emperors (qayṣar) and Sassanian kings (kisrā) as  exemplifying a form of royal rule incompatible with the principles of  Islam.87 However, whereas the Persian Empire proved very vulnerable  to Muslim attacks and quickly fell under the sway of Islam, Byzantium  in the aftermath of the Arabs’ efforts to capture Constantinople, especially in the tenth century, came to be widely perceived as a resilient  political and military power that posed a formidable and lasting chal lenge to its Arab neighbors and that would perish only with the coming  of the Day of Judgment.88 Al-Jāḥiẓ (781–869) notes that Mu‘āwiyah’s  (602–680, r. 661–680) ascension to power as the first Caliph of the  Umayyad dynasty marked a period of oppression and violence in which  the imamate mutated into a kind of kingdom as the one during Chos roes’s reign and the caliphate degenerated into a tyranny that only per tained to a caesar (≈ Byzantine emperor).89

Arab authors also denounced luxury, wasteful extravagance, pomp,  and overtaxation as symptoms of the devolution of Byzantine author ity. The geographer and  traveler  Ibn Ḥawqal (tenth century)  reports  that in an effort to cover the expenses of his military expeditions  against the Muslims Emperor Nikephoros II Phokas (912–969, r. 963– 969) imposed heavy taxes instead of using his own funds and provoked  popular discontent and agitation which led to his assassination.90 Such  an assessment persisted down to the fourteenth century as indicated by  the characterization of the Byzantines as ungenerous and self-conceited  in al-Nuwayrī’s (d. 1333) history of the Mongol conquest of Syria.91 Ibn  Khaldūn  (1332–1406) likewise observes that whereas Muslims were  originally averse to royal decorum and pomp, the caliphate gradually  mutated into royal rule and Muslims paid increasing attention to splen dor and developed a penchant for luxury, especially after inter acting  and mingling with Persians and Byzantines who displayed to them  their ways of ostentation and luxury.92 Finally, an interesting precedent  to Shāh Walī Allāh’s ideas on the Byzantine practice of imperial power  may be found in the Talkhīṣ kitāb al-khiṭābah li-Arisṭū (Middle Com mentary on Aristotle’s Rhetoric) of the famous Arab philosopher Ibn  Rushd (Averroes, 1126–1198): elaborating on Aristotle’s typology of  the various regime types, Ibn Rushd distinguishes between cities that  are ruled according to fixed and immutable laws, as is the case with the  Islamic law, and cities whose laws change according to what is most  expedient, as is the case with many of the laws in Byzantium.93

Assessing the veracity of Shāh Walī Allāh’s account of Byzantine  decline would require a closer survey of the image of the Byzantine  Empire in medieval and early modern Islamic writing, especially in the  central and eastern lands of Islam, that exceeds the scope of this arti cle.94 It is possible that Shāh Walī Allāh’s intention is to alert Mughal  rulers to the imminent fall of the empire by invoking Byzantium as a  negative example of a great imperial state that collapsed due to an eco nomic crisis very similar to the one that afflicted eighteenth-century  India.95 Even so, Shāh Walī Allāh’s statements attest to a keen aware ness and appreciation of the economic factors involved in the decline  of Byzantine power and the affinities between Mughal and Byzantine  political realities and calls for a comparative study of Mughal and   Byzantine reactions to the phenomenon of imperial decline. As noted earlier, a number of medieval Islamic accounts of the   Byzantine Empire centered around excessive taxation as one of the  major flaws of Byzantine imperial administration. Just like Ibn Ḥawqal,  who ascribed the social tensions that arose during Nikephoros Pho kas’s reign to high taxation and the exploitation of the people, John  Skylitzes (late eleventh century) mentions in his Synopsis Historiōn (A  Synopsis of Histories) that Phokas, who was vilified by some of his  contemporaries as a belligerent ruler, incurred the hatred of his subjects  by imposing excessive taxation and turning a blind eye to the abuses  of the military and the plundering and pillage of the people’s prop erty. Skylitzes denounces Phokas’s policies to create additional sources  of revenues and raise supplement taxes: in particular, he criticizes the  Byzantine emperor for abrogating some of the financial benefits of the  members of the senate on the pretext of lacking funds to sustain the  war effort, terminating the financial aid offered to religious houses and  churches, and passing a law that prohibited the expansion of ecclesias tical property. Last but not least, the emperor caused the devaluation  of the existing currency (nomisma) by introducing an additional form  of currency, the tetarteron.96

The degeneration of Byzantine political strength was visible as  early as the eleventh century,97 as evidenced by Michael Attaleiates’s  (1020/1030–1085) references to misgovernment and venality in the  imperial administration as the prime causes of Byzantine decadence  especially in the aftermath of the Byzantine army’s defeat by Seljuq  forces at the battle of Mantzikert (Malazgirt, 1071) and the Turkish  occupation of a large part of Asia Minor.98 In his Historia (History)  Attaleiates berates the Byzantine rulers and court officials for engaging  in impious and illicit activities in the name of the public welfare. Attaleiates also outlines the process whereby Byzantine military fortunes  reached a low ebb as the army leaders were concerned solely with mak ing profit and shirked their duties and the soldiers imitated the conduct  of their commanders, behaving in an unjust and cruel manner toward  the people and seeking to destroy, usurp, or plunder their property as if  they were the enemies of their own country.99

The steady increase of costs for the administration and sustenance  of the Byzantine army, for luxury, finery, and pomp, coincided with  Venice’s and Genoa’s dominance in Mediterranean trade. With the  Turkish menace looming large in the mid thirteenth century, some of  the protagonists of late Byzantine intellectual and religious life engaged  in sustained reflection on the causes and effects of the factional strife  that raged through the empire. Tirades against profit making, injustice,  and  rampant corruption were common. Similar  to Shāh Walī Allāh,  who identified tax burdens laid on the peasantry and the parasitic  activities of religious figures as two of the major reasons for imperial  decline, a number of Byzantine political theorists blamed the economic  problems of the empire on the exploitation of the productive classes  and on the tax privileges of the monasteries.100

Amidst a famine in Constantinople in the 1300s, the then Patri arch of Constantinople (1289–1293 and 1303–1309), Athanasios I  (1230/35–ca. 1323), addressed a number of letters to the Byzantine  emperor Andronikos II Palaiologos (1259–1332; r. 1282–1328) in  which he makes an impassioned plea for the fair distribution of food  supplies:101 just as the sun radiates warmth, so too is one of the emper or’s prime tasks to uphold security and justice. Athanasios specifically  calls upon the emperor to restrain those who, driven by greed, seek to  profiteer by hoarding for themselves public revenues and inflict pov erty102 and recommends drastic measures against those who receive  bribes and slander the Church.103 He advocates tight central control  over the purchase of grain and bread104 and the judicious selection of  revenue collectors.105 He also calls for strict monitoring of the bakers  and of the transportation and delivery of grain so that cargoes do not  end up in the hands of grain dealers and profiteers but are distributed to  those who are in need of food,106 and he threatens to excommunicate  all grain dealers.107

Economic inequities and the outbreak of the Zealot revolution in  Thessalonike, the empire’s second most important city after Constan tinople, provoked intense debates on the political and social maladies  that afflicted the Byzantine state in the first half of the fourteenth cen tury.108 Following Emperor Andronikos III Palaiologos’s (1296–1341,  r. 1328–1341) death in June 1341, his chief minister, John Kan ta kouzenos (1292–1383), served as the effective regent for John V (1332– 1391), Andronikos’s infant son, and proclaimed himself emperor four  months later. In 1342, a political group that called themselves Zealots  and were led by the grand duke (= commander-in-chief of the Byzan tine navy) Alexios Apokaukos (late thirteenth century–1345) set up  a popular regime in Thessalonike. The conflict touched off a series of  revolts in other cities, with the nobility backing Kantakouzenos and  the middle and lower classes supporting John V and the Zealots. The  Zealot regime came to an end when Kantakouzenos recovered Thes salonike in 1350.

Nikephoros Choumnos’s (1250/55–1327) speech Thessalonikeusi  sum vouleutikos peri Dikaiosunēs (Exhortatory Oration on Justice) pro vides intriguing insights into the background of the events surrounding  the Zealot movement and a vivid description of the poverty conditions  and inequality in late Byzantine Thessalonike.109 Choumnos, a distin guished scholar and prime minister (mesazōn) of Emperor Andronikos  II, served as governor of Thessalonike in 1309/10.110 The speech, writ ten most probably around 1284/85,111 was originally intended for the  citizens of Thessalonike, but it was never delivered in public and circu lated within Choumnos’s circle of friends and associates.112 Choumnos  castigates the rich for contriving to take over the property and houses  of the poor in order to build their luxurious multi-storey residences and  points out that the poor in their turn, though initially trying to nego tiate, become desperate and succumb to the demands of those who,  driven by covetousness and cupidity, seek to seize their property.113 Similar sentiments are echoed in Tois Thessalonikeusi peri omonoias ([Oration] to the Citizens of Thessalonike on Concord),114 an exhorta tory speech composed by Thomas Magister (or Magistros, also known  by his monastic name Theodoulos, ca. 1280–1350/51), an eminent  classical scholar and theologian.115 The speech draws to some extent  on ancient Greek models, especially Aelius Aristides’s (117 c.e.–after  181) orations, and captures the sense of anguish and the political dec adence that prevailed in Thessalonike in the wake of the civil wars  between Andronikos II and his grandson Andronikos III over the  succession to the throne during the years 1321–1328 and on the eve  of the Zealot revolution.116 Magister also wrote two treatises on the  proper qualifications for kingship (Peri vasileias [On Kingship]) and the  duties of citizens (Peri politeias [On the Commonwealth]),117 in which  he makes an urgent appeal to the civic body of Thessalonike to restore  unity and uphold justice, and alerting readers to the deleterious effects  of sedition and factional discord (stasis).

The theme of economic injustice was seconded by Alexios Makrem volites (d. after 1349), who offers a prescient analysis of the fall of  the Byzantine state as the result of a decision of the world-governing 

Providence that causes the fluctuations in the affairs of the world and  transfers sovereignty from one people to another. In the fictional Dialo gos plousiōn kai penētōn (Dialogue [between] Rich and Poor, ca. 1344),  Makremvolites captures the feverish strife and social rifts that con vulsed the Byzantine world in the thirteenth century and points to the  suffering of the poor, who were at the mercy of the wealthy.118 Another major late Byzantine intellectual who witnessed the reper cussions of the Zealot episode and got embroiled in contemporary  debates on the economic and social ills that plagued the empire was  Nikolaos Kavasilas (ca. 1322–ca. 1390), a cleric and scion of a promi nent noble family from Thessalonike. In his Peri tokou (On Interest),  an oration addressed to Anna of Savoy (Palaiologina, 1306–ca. 1365)  that was written around 1351, he expresses unqualified disdain for the  rich who, as he observes, engage in unjust actions, seek profit by ruin ing others, and behave like robbers, thieves, and wild animals.119 In his Logos kata tokizontōn (Oration against Usurers), Kavasilas 

offers an extensive treatment of lending at interest and hoarding of  resources onto which he has grafted patristic and legal definitions  of usury. He also points to the moral dimensions of usury, which he  equates with other kinds of crimes such as adultery, murder, and theft,  with the only difference that these crimes entail a certain degree of  risk, whereas usury is a more detestable form of crime because it is free  of risks.120 Kava silas specifically denounces laws that associate interest  rates and the character of the lender and forbid clerics from loaning  at interest or allow nobles to charge only low rates while permitting  wicked and morally corrupt individuals to charge high interest rates.121

If the Zealot rebellion was construed by both pro- and anti-Zealot  intellectuals as a portent of Byzantium’s fall, in the first half of the  fourteenth century the political disintegration of Byzantine rule due  to the wrongs and injustices perpetuated by the imperial administration, a long series of economic crises, and the advances of the Turk ish forces came to be broadly regarded as a fait accompli. A number  of Byzantine thinkers felt despondent about the process of Byzantine  decline, explaining it as a manifestation of divine wrath for misrule or  a divine punishment for the Byzantines’ refusal to endorse the union  of the churches.122 But George Gemistos Plethon (d. 1452), a towering  figure of late Byzantine intellectual life and purveyor of ancient Greek  and Byzantine learning in Renaissance Italy, pinned his hopes for sur vival on the organization of the Peloponnese as an autonomous politi cal entity that would serve as the last refuge for Byzantines of “Hellenic”  stock, as shown in the two memoranda which he addressed to Theodoros  II Palaiologos (1396–1448, r. 1407–1443), Despot of Mystra, in 1416,123 and Emperor Manuel II Palaiologos (1350–1425, r. 1391–1421) in  1418.124

The ideal form of regime envisioned by Plethon is one with a strong  monarch with a moderate number of educated men drawn from the  middle class acting as his advisers. Plethon also advocates abolition  of private property, regulation of commercial activities with an eye to  local needs, and strict currency control.125

Conclusion

In this article, I elucidated the central premises of Shāh Walī Allāh’s  theory of the state and human civilization and engaged in a closer  discussion of the ways in which his political ideas relate to previous  Islamic political discourse, notably the akhlāq  (Ṭūsī,  Dawwānī)  and  Indo-Islamic  strands of political  thought (Baranī, Abū’l-Faẓl, Najm-i  Sānī). I demonstrated that Shāh Walī Allāh articulates a naturalistic  approach to the phenomenon of social genesis and posits the goal of  meeting human needs as the prime motivating force behind the formation of human society.

I also reconstructed Shāh Walī Allāh’s theory about the factors that  account for the decline of the state and the empire and of his program  for dealing with a broad range of emergencies. I argued that Shāh Walī Allāh’s statements on the causes of Mughal decay open a window into the intellectual atmosphere in the last centuries of Mughal rule, but  also bear intriguing affinities to the ideas expressed by earlier thinkers  on the economic aspects of imperial decline. Shāh Walī Allāh’s use of  the Byzantine paradigm as an instrument of analysis of the sociopo litical conditions that prevailed in his contemporary India brings him  close to a number of Byzantine authors who perceived the eclipse of  Byzantine rule as the outcome of social inequalities, oppression of the  lower strata of society, and overtaxation. Moreover,  the  findings  of  the  preceding  analysis  of  Shāh  Walī  Allāh’s political thought call for a reassessment of Bernard Lewis’s the sis that the decline of the Islamic world occurred due to intrinsic flaws  in the Islamic tradition, notably the status of slaves, women, and unbe lievers,126 and cultural obstinacy and aversion to secularization.127 Shāh  Walī Allāh is in substantial agreement with Byzantine thinkers on the  primacy of economic factors in the process of imperial decline. His ref erences to the Byzantine and Sassanian empires reflect a vivid aware ness of the importance of maladministration and financial corruption  as universal causes for the decay of any type of state organization that  extends well beyond the Islamic context.

While previous scholarly attempts to study the history of the  Mughal Empire from a cross-cultural perspective have primarily  focused on comparisons with the Roman and Ottoman empires,128 the  results of this article highlight the need for a detailed investigation  of Indo-Islamic attitudes toward the political history of the Byzantine  Empire and a comparative study of the Byzantine and Mughal pat terns of imperial organization. They also call for a critical reevaluation  of  Shāh Walī  Allāh’s  political  ideas  and  philosophy  of  history  that  will help place him in conversation with eighteenth-century Western  thinkers (Montesquieu, Vico, Gibbon) and revisit the relevance of his  ideas to ongoing debates on the economic dimensions of state decline.

 

Notes

 

* Thanks are due to Muzaffar Alam, Razi Aquil, Christos Baloglou, Jonathan Har ris, Anthony Kaldellis, Dimitris Krallis, and Niketas Siniossoglou for reading drafts of the  paper and offering valuable feedback. I would also like to acknowledge the financial support  provided by the Centre of Excellence in Political Thought and Conceptual Change of the  Academy of Finland (2008–2011) and the Marty Martin Center for the Advanced Study of  Religion at the University of Chicago (2010/2011).

1  For  an  intriguing  comparison  of  Shāh  Walī  Allāh’s  and  Jean-Jacques  Rousseau’s  (1712–1778) ideas, see Jacques Berque, L’islam au temps du monde (Paris: Sindbad, 1984),  chap. “Un contemporain islamo-indien de Jean-Jacques Rousseau,” pp. 113–146. Early  modern European perceptions of the Mughal Empire are surveyed in Frederick G. Whelan,  Enlightenment Political Thought and Non-Western Societies: Sultans and Savages (New York:  Routledge, 2009), esp. chap. “Burke, India, and Orientalism,” pp. 103–129.

2  On Shāh Walī Allāh’s life and works, see Mawlavi M. Hidayat Husain, “The Persian  Autobiography  of  Shāh Walīullah  bin  ‘Abd  al-Raḥīm  al-Dihlavī:  Its  English Translation  and a List of His Works,” Journal of the Asiatic Society of Bengal 8 (1912): 161–175; as well  as Jens Bakker, Šāh Walīy Allāh ad-Dihlawīy (1703–1762) und sein Aufenthalt in Mekka und  Medina: Ein Beitrag zur Erforschung des islamischen Reformdenkens im frühen 18. Jahrhundert (Berlin: EB-Verleg, 2010); Ghulam H. Jalbani, Life of Shah Waliyullah (Lahore: Sh. Muham

mad Ashraf, 1978); Fazle Mahmud, “An Exhaustive Study of the Life of Shah Wali Allah  Dehlavi,” Oriental College Magazine 33 (1956): 1–45; as well as the following articles in  M. Ikram Chaghatai, ed., Shah Waliullah (1703–1762): His Religious and Political Thought (Lahore: Sang-e-Meel Publications, 2005; henceforth SWRPT): Marcia K. Hermansen,  “Shāh Walī Allāh” (pp. 11–14); A. S. Bazmee Ansari, “Shah Wali Allah al-Dihlawi” (pp.  15–18); Bashir A. Dar, “Wali Allah: His Life and Times” (pp. 19–50; first published in Iqbal  Review 6, no. 3 [1965]: 1–36); Abdul H. Siddiqi, “Shah Wali Allah Dihlawi” (pp. 51–77;  first published in Mian M. Sharif, ed., A History of Muslim Philosophy: With Short Accounts of  Other Disciplines and the Modern Renaissance in Muslim Lands [Wiesbaden: O. Harrassowitz,  1966], 2:1557–1579); and Alessandro Bausani, “Note su Shāh Walīullāh di Delhi (1703– 1762),” Annali dell’ Istituto Orientale di Napoli, n.s., 10 (1960): 93–147. Also broadly on the  intellectual climate in Shāh Walī Allāh’s time, consult Saiyid A. A. Rizvi, Shāh Walī-Allāh  and His Times: A Study of Eighteenth Century Islām, Politics and Society in India (Canberra:  Ma’rifat Publishing House, 1980), esp. pp. 111–202; and, in general, Peter J. Marshall, ed.,  The Eighteenth Century in Indian History: Evolution or Revolution? (New Delhi: Oxford University Press, 2003); Seema Alavi, ed., The Eighteenth Century in India (New Delhi: Oxford  University Press, 2002).

3  Shāh Walī  Allāh ibn  ‘Abd  al-Raḥīm, Ḥujjat Allāh al-Bālighah, 2  vols.  (Cairo:  Dār  al-Turāth,  1978); English trans.: The Conclusive Argument from God: Shāh Walī Allāh of  Delhi’s Ḥujjat Allāh al-Bāligha, trans. Marcia K. Hermansen (Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1996; repr., Islamabad: International Islamic University, Islamic Research Institute, 2003). I have relied  on the English translations of some of the Arabic, Persian, and Byzantine sources mentioned  throughout this paper with some amendments not indicated due to space limitations. On  the Ḥujjat Allāh al-Bālighah, see the following chapters in SWRPT: Marcia K. Hermansen,  “Shah Wali Allah’s Hujjat Allah al-Baligha” (pp. 529–552); Hermansen, “Shāh Walī Allāh  of Delhi’s Ḥujjat Allāh al-Bāligha: Tension between the Universal and the Particular in an  Eighteenth-Century Islamic Theory of Religious Revelation” (pp. 597–614; first published  in Studia Islamica 63 [1986]: 143–157); Sabih A. Kamali, “The Concept of Human Nature  in Ḥujjat Allāh al-Bālighah and  Its Relation  to Shāh Walīy Allāh’s Doctrine of Fiqh” (pp.  553–596; first published in Islamic Culture 36, no. 3 [1962]: 207–224; 36, no. 4 [1962]:  256–274); as well as Fazle Mahmud, “Shah Wali Allah’s Hujjatullahil balighah,” Journal of  the Arabic and Persian Society of the Panjab University 5, no. 4/6:1 (1960/61): 1–28.

4 Shah Waliyullah, Al-Budur al-Bāzighah, trans. Ghulam N. Jalbani, 2nd ed. (New  Delhi: Kitab Bhavan, 2005); Full Moon Appearing on the Horizon: English Translation of Shah  Wali Allah (Al-Budur al-Bazighah), trans. Johannes M. S. Baljon (Lahore: Sh. Muhammad  Ashraf, 1990). On the Al-Budūr al-Bāzighah as a source of Shah Walī Allāh’s political ideas,  see  Saeeda Khatoon,  “Shāh Walī  Allāh’s  Philosophy  of  Society—an  Outline,” Hamdard  Islamicus 7, no. 4 (1984): 57–67, repr. in SWRPT, pp. 421–431; Ghulam N. Jalbani, Teachings of Shāh Walīyullāh of Delhi (Lahore: Sh. Muhammad Ashraf, 1967; repr., New Delhi:  Nusrat Ali Nasri Lor Kitab Bhavan, 1988), pp. 126–147; Muhammad ‘A. Baqi, “Theories  of State and Problems of Sociology as Expounded by an Indian Muslim Divine of the Eigh teenth Century,” Islamic Review 38 (1950): 9–14. A comparative study of the Ḥujjat Allāh  al-Bāli ghah and Al-Budūr al-Bāzighah remains a desideratum.

5 Ayesha Jalal, Partisans of Allah: Jihad in South Asia (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard Uni versity Press, 2008), pp. 40–57. Consider also Muhammad T. Mallick, “Rationale of Jihād as  Expounded  by  Shāh Walī Allāh  of Delhi,” Journal of the Pakistan Historical Society 34 (1986): 14–25.

6 See, for example, Mahmood A. Ghazi, Islamic Renaissance in South Asia 1707–1867:  The Role of Shāh Walī Allāh and His Successors (Islamabad: Islamic Research Institute/Inter national Islamic University, 2002); Ahmad Dallal, “The Origins and Objectives of Islamic  Revivalist Thought, 1750–1850,” Journal of the American Oriental Society 113 (1993): 341– 359; Muhammad al-Faruque, “Some Aspects of Muslim Revivalist Movements in India  During the 18th Century: The Activities of Shāh Walī-Allāh of Delhi,” Islamic Culture 63 (1989): 19–41; Shafi A. Khan, “Nationalist ‘Ulama’s Interpretation of Shāh Walī Allah’s  Thought and Movement,” Journal of the Pakistan Historical Society 37 (1989): 209–248;  Saiyid Athar Abbas Rizvi, Muslim Revivalist Movements in Northern India in the Sixteenth and  Seventeenth Centuries (Agra: Agra University Press, 1965; repr., New Delhi: M. Manoharlal,  1993).

7  Shāh Walī Allāh uses the Arabic term madīnah, which literally means “city” and is  roughly equivalent to the Greek polis, in the sense of a political entity that encompasses a  number of cities and is characterized by an administrative and governmental organization  similar to that of the modern state. Accordingly, Shāh Walī Allāh envisions the caliphate as  incorporating a multiplicity of existing states and political units. On the meaning of madīna  and its derivatives in medieval Arab political writing, see Soheil M. Afnan, A Philosophical  Lexicon in Persian and Arabic (Beirut: Imprimerie Catholique, 1969; repr., Tehran: Nashr-i  Nuqrih, 1362 [1983]), s.v. madīna (278–279); Dimitri Gutas, “The Meaning of madīnah in  al-Fārābī’s ‘Political’ Philosophy,” in The Greek Strand in Islamic Political Thought, ed. Emma  Gannagé et al. (= Mélanges de l’Université Saint-Joseph; 57; Beirut: Dār el-Machreq, 2004),  pp. 259–279. For a useful orientation to the various definitions of the concept of “empire,”  consult Kathleen D. Morrison, “Sources, Approaches, Definitions,” in Empires: Perspectives  from Archaeology and History, ed. Susan E. Alcock et al. (Cambridge: Cambridge University  Press, 2001), pp. 1–9, esp. 1–3.

8 Given the enormous amount of scholarship on imperial ascendancy and decline, I  confine myself to mentioning some of the most important studies I consulted in the process  of writing this paper: Niall Ferguson, “Complexity and Collapse: Empires on the Edge of  Chaos,” Foreign Affairs 89, no. 2 (2010): 18–32; Peter Turchin, Historical Dynamics: Why  States Rise and Fall (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 2003); Alexander J. Motyl,  Imperial Ends: The Decay, Collapse, and Revival of Empires (New York: Columbia University  Press, 2001); Motyl, “Thinking about Empire,” in After Empire: Multiethnic Societies and  Nation-Building: The Soviet Union and the Russian, Ottoman, and Habsburg Empires, ed. Karen  Barkey and Mark von Hagen (Boulder, Colo.: Westview Press, 1997), pp. 19–29; Charles  Tilly, “How Empires End,” in Barkey and von Hagen, After Empire, pp. 1–11; Emil Brix et  al., eds., The Decline of Empires (Vienna: Verlag für Geschichte und Politik; Munich: Olden-bourg Verlag, 2001); Richard Lorenz, ed., Das Verdämmern der Macht: Vom Untergang grosser  Reiche (Frankfurt a. M.: Fischer TB Verlag, 2000); Paul M. Kennedy, The Rise and Fall of the  Great Powers: Economic Change and Military Conflict from 1500 to 2000 (New York: Ran dom House, 1987); Joseph A. Tainter, The Collapse of Complex Societies (Cambridge: Cam bridge University Press, 1988); Michael W. Doyle, Empires (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University  Press, 1986); Carlo M. Cipolla, ed., The Economic Decline of Empires (London: Methuen,  1970); Shmuel N. Eisenstadt, ed., The Decline of Empires (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice Hall, 1967); Shmuel N. Eisenstadt, The Political Systems of Empires (London: Free Press of  Glencoe, 1963; repr., New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers, 1993); and Geir Lundestad,  ed., The Fall of Great Powers: Peace, Stability, and Legitimacy (Oslo: Scandinavian Univer sity Press, 1994). For stimulating reflections on the history of empires and its relevance to  current debates on the role of the United States as a global power, see Craig Calhoun et  al., eds., Lessons of Empire: Imperial Histories and American Power (New York: New Press,  2006). The phenomenon of state failure is discussed in Robert I. Rotberg, ed., When States  Fail: Causes and Consequences (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 2004). On the  theme of decline, consult, e.g., Daron Acemoglu and James A. Robinson, Why Nations Fail:  The Origins of Power, Prosperity and Poverty (New York: Crown Publishers, 2012); Rein hart Koselleck and Paul Widmer, eds., Niedergang: Studien zu einem geschichtlichen Thema (Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta, 1980); Peter Burke, “Tradition and Experience: The Idea of Decline  from Bruni to Gibbon,” in Edward Gibbon and the Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire, ed. Glenn W. Bowersock et al. (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1977), pp.  87–102; Randolph Starn, “Meaning-Levels in the Theme of Historical Decline,” History  and Theory 14 (1975): 1–31.

9  On  the  sources  of  Shāh Walī  Allāh’s  political  ideas,  see  the  remarks  by Muzaffar  Alam, The Languages of Political Islam: India 1200–1800 (London: Hurst, 2004), pp. 50,  171–173; as well as Muhammad al-Ghazali, The Socio-Political Thought of Shāh Walī Allāh (Islamabad: International Institute of Islamic Thought and Islamic Research Institute,  2001; repr., New Delhi: Adam Publishers and Distributors, 2004), pp. 33–43; and Saiyid A.  A. Rizvi, “The Political Thoughts of Shāh Walī Allāh,” Abr-Nahrain 16 (1975/76): 91–107,  91–92, repr. in SWRPT, pp. 277–308. A general treatment of Shāh Walī Allāh’s political  theory can be found in Mahmood A. Ghazi, “State and Politics in the Philosophy of Shah  Waliy Allah,” Islamic Studies 23 (1984): 353–371, repr. in SWRPT, pp. 225–241.

10 For a similar interpretation, see Johannes M. S. Baljon, “Social and Economic Ideas  of Shah Wali Allah,” in Readings in Islamic Economic Thought, ed. Abul Hasan M. Sadeq and  Aidit Ghazali (Dhaka: Islamic Foundation Bangladesh, 2006), pp. 356–368, 358. The term  irtifāq (literal meaning: support) derives from the Arabic root r.f.q., which signifies kindness  or gentleness. For further discussion, see Hermansen, The Conclusive Argument from God,pp. xviii–xix.

11 Waliyullah, Al-Budūr al-Bāzighah, pp. 48–49; Baljon, Full Moon Appearing on the  Horizon, pp. 56–58. See further Abdul A. Islahi, “Shah Wali Allah’s Concept of Al-Irtifaqat  (Stages of Socio-Economic Development),” Journal of Objective Studies 1–2 (1990): 46–63,  51 (repr. in Fazlur R. Faridi, ed., Aspects of Islamic Economics and the Economy of IndianMuslims [New Delhi: Institute of Objective Studies, 1993], pp. 73–93); as well as Sabih A.  Kamali, “Shah Waliy Allah’s Doctrine of Irtifaqat,” Iqbal 11, no. 3 (1963): 1–17, repr. in  SWRPT, pp. 401–420.

12 Ḥujjat Allāh al-Bālighah, 1:39; Hermansen, The Conclusive Argument from God, pp.  117–118.

13 Ḥujjat Allāh al-Bālighah, 1:38; Hermansen, The Conclusive Argument from God, pp.  115–116; Waliyullah, Al-Budūr al-Bāzighah, pp. 22–23; Baljon, Full Moon Appearing on the  Horizon, p. 32. See also the discussion in Johannes M. S. Baljon, “The Ethics of Shâh Walî  Allâh Dihlawî (1703–62),” in Akten des VII. Kongresses für Arabistik und Islamwissenschaft,

ed. Albert Dietrich (Göttingen: Vandenhoeck und Ruprecht, 1976), pp. 66–73, 67–69, repr.  in SWRPT, pp. 397–405.

14 Ḥujjat Allāh al-Bālighah, 1:39; Hermansen, The Conclusive Argument from God, p. 117. 15 Ḥujjat Allāh al-Bālighah, 1:40; Hermansen, The Conclusive Argument from God, p. 121. 16 Ḥujjat Allāh al-Bālighah, 1:39–40; Hermansen, The Conclusive Argument from God,

p. 119; Waliyullah, Al-Budūr al-Bāzighah, pp. 53–54; Baljon, Full Moon Appearing on the  Horizon, pp. 61–63.

17 Ḥujjat Allāh al-Bālighah, 1:40; Hermansen, The Conclusive Argument from God, pp.  119–120.

18 Compare Plato, Politeia, 372A–374E.

19 Ḥujjat Allāh al-Bālighah, 1:41–42; Hermansen, The Conclusive Argument from God, p. 127.

20 Ḥujjat Allāh al-Bālighah, 1:43–44; Hermansen, The Conclusive Argument from God, p. 128.

21 Ḥujjat Allāh al-Bālighah, 1:42; Hermansen, The Conclusive Argument from God, p. 127. 22 Ḥujjat Allāh al-Bālighah, 1:45; Hermansen, The Conclusive Argument from God, p. 129. 23 Ḥujjat Allāh al-Bālighah, 1:45; Hermansen, The Conclusive Argument from God, p. 132.

24 Ḥujjat Allāh al-Bālighah, 1:45–46; Hermansen, The Conclusive Argument from God, pp. 132–133; Waliyullah, Al-Budūr al-Bāzighah, pp. 79–81; Baljon, Full Moon Appearing on  the Horizon, pp. 86–88.

25 Ḥujjat Allāh al-Bālighah, 1:46; Hermansen, The Conclusive Argument from God, p. 133.

24 Ḥujjat Allāh al-Bālighah, 1:45–46; Hermansen, The Conclusive Argument from God, pp. 132–133; Waliyullah, Al-Budūr al-Bāzighah, pp. 79–81; Baljon, Full Moon Appearing on  the Horizon, pp. 86–88.

25 Ḥujjat Allāh al-Bālighah, 1:46; Hermansen, The Conclusive Argument from God, p. 133.

26 Waliyullah, Al-Budūr al-Bāzighah, pp. 77–78; Baljon, Full Moon Appearing on the  Horizon, pp. 85–86.

27 Ḥujjat Allāh al-Bālighah, 1:46; Hermansen, The Conclusive Argument from God, p. 134. 28 Ḥujjat Allāh al-Bālighah, 1:46–47; Hermansen, The Conclusive Argument from God, pp. 135–136; Waliyullah, Al-Budūr al-Bāzighah, pp. 94–96; Baljon, Full Moon Appearing on  the Horizon, pp. 99–101.

29 Waliyullah, Al-Budūr al-Bāzighah, pp. 94–95; Baljon, Full Moon Appearing on the  Horizon, p. 100.

30 Ḥujjat Allāh al-Bālighah, 1:46; Hermansen, The Conclusive Argument from God, pp.  134–135.

31 Ḥujjat Allāh al-Bālighah, 1:46; Hermansen, The Conclusive Argument from God, p. 135.

32 Ḥujjat Allāh al-Bālighah, 1:45; Hermansen, The Conclusive Argument from God, p.  137. See also Waliyullah, Al-Budūr al-Bāzighah, pp. 97–98; Baljon, Full Moon Appearing on  the Horizon, pp. 101–103.

33  On  the  reception  of  al-Fārābī’s  political ideas in  the  Indo-Islamic world  as medi ated  by Ṭūsī’s Nasirean Ethics, see Saiyid A. A. Rizvi, Religious and Intellectual History of  the Muslims in Akbar’s Reign, with Special Reference to Abuʾl Fazl (1556–1605) (New Delhi:  M. Manoharlal Publishers, 1975), pp. 355–357.

34 Al-Farabi on the Perfect State: Abū Naṣr al-Fārābī’s Mabādiʾ ārāʾ ahl al-madīna al-fāḍila.  A revised text with introduction, translation, and commentary by Richard Walzer (Oxford:  Clarendon Press, 1985; repr., Chicago: KAZI Publications, 1998), Arabic text p. 228,   English trans. p. 229. Consider also Al-Farabi, The Political Writings: Selected Aphorisms and  Other Texts, trans. Charles E. Butterworth (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 2001),  pp. 23–26, 46. For further discussion, see Patricia Crone, God’s Rule: Government and Islam (New York: Columbia University Press, 2004), pp. 177, 260–261, 343; Shlomo Pines, “The  Societies Providing for the Bare Necessities of Life According to Ibn Khaldūn and to the  Philosophers,” Studia Islamica 34 (1971): 125–138, repr., in Pines, The Collected Works of  Shlomo Pines, vol. 3, Studies in the History of Arabic Philosophy, ed. Sarah Stroumsa (Jerusa

lem: Magnes Press, 1996), pp. 217–230.

35 Al-Farabi on the Perfect State, p. 230/231, as well as pp. 424, 432–433, 497.

36 The following account is based on Abdur R. Bhat, Political Thought of Shah Waliul lâh (An Analytical Study) (New Delhi: Delhi, Rightway Publication, 2002), chap. “Shah  Waliullah’s Political Theory in Islamic Context,” pp. 65–73; Aziz Ahmad, “An Eighteenth Century Theory of the Caliphate,” Studia Islamica 28 (1968): 135–144. Consider also  Johannes M. S. Baljon, Religion and Thought of Shāh Walī Allāh Dihlawī, 1703–1762 (Leiden:  E. J. Brill, 1986), pp. 121–125, 195–196.

37 A precedent of this distinction can be found in the Fatāwā-i-Jahāndārī (Precepts on  [World] Rulership) of Ziyā’ al-Dīn Baranī (1284–1356), a confidant of the sultan of Delhi  Muḥammad bin Tughluq (ca. 1300–1351, r. 1325–1351) and major historian of fourteenth century  India:  Baranī  distinguishes  two forms  of justice,  one  that  aims  at  general  equal ity (‘adl-i musāwāt-i talabī-yi ‘ām) and one concerned with special equality (adl-i musāwāt-i  talabī-yi khāss). The former is the ideal form of justice, can be realized only in the Islamic  setting, and was exemplified by Caliph ‘Umar (ca. 586–644, r. 634–644). The latter was  applied by the Persian king Anūshirwān (Chosroes I, r. 531–579) and presupposes the exis tence of a ruler acting as an arbitrator and settling disputes. For further references and com ment, see Alam, The Languages of Political Islam, pp. 38–39.

38 Ḥujjat Allāh al-Bālighah, 1:48–49; Hermansen, The Conclusive Argument from God, pp. 138–139.

39 Aristotle, Politics 1253a1–3. On the following, see also Vasileios Syros, “Shadows in  Heaven and Clouds on Earth: The Emergence of Social Life and Political Authority in the  Early Modern Islamic Empires,” Viator 43, no. 2 (2012): 377–406.

40  Naṣīr al-Ṭūsī, Akhlāq-i Nāṣirī (Lahore: Punjab University, 1952), p. 242; The Nasirean  Ethics by Naṣīr ad-Dīn Ṭūsī, trans. from the Persian George M. Wickens (London: Allen and  Unwin, 1964), p. 189. See also Guang-Zhen Sun, “Nasir ad-Din Tusi on Social Coopera tion and the Division of Labor: Fragment from The Nasirean Ethics,” Journal of Institutional  Economics 5 (2008): 403–413.

41  Al-Ṭūsī, Akhlāq-i Nāṣirī, p. 243; The Nasirean Ethics, pp. 190–191. 42  [Jalāl al-Dīn Dawwānī], Practical Philosophy of the Muhammadan People, trans. W. F.  Thompson (London: W. H. Allen, 1839; repr., Karachi: Karimsons, 1977); The English Trans lation of the Akhlak-i-Jalali: A Code of Morality in Persian composed by Jalal-ud-Din Moham mad Alias Allama Dawwani, trans. S. H. Deen (Lahore: Sh. Mubarak Ali, 1939). Scholarly  discussions of Dawwānī’s political ideas include Erwin  I.  J. Rosenthal, Political Thought in  Medieval Islam: An Introductory Outline (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1958),  chap.  “Al-Dawwāni: Application  and  Integration,”  pp.  210–223; Mohammed-Taqi Dan ishpazhouh, “An Annotated Bibliography on Government and Statecraft,” trans. Andrew  Newman, in Authority and Political Culture in Shi‘ism, ed. Said Amir Arjomand (Albany:  State University of New York Press, 1988), pp. 213–239, esp. 221–222; Muhammad A. Haq,  “A Critical Study of  Jalāl al-Dīn al-Dawwāni’s Contribution  to Social Philosophy” (PhD  diss., Aligarh Muslim University, n.d.).

43 Practical Philosophy of the Muhammadan People, pp. 318–320, 245–250; Deen, The  English Translation of the Akhlak-i-Jalali, pp. 161–162, 126–128.

44 Practical Philosophy of the Muhammadan People, p. 321; Deen, The English Translation  of the Akhlak-i-Jalali, p. 163.

45 Practical Philosophy of the Muhammadan People, p. 322; Deen, The English Translation  of the Akhlak-i-Jalali, p. 163.

46 Practical Philosophy of the Muhammadan People, pp. 324–325; Deen, The English Trans lation of the Akhlak-i-Jalali, pp. 164–165.

47 Alam, The Languages of Political Islam, p. 50; Alam, “State Building under the  Mughals: Religion, Culture and Politics,” in L’Héritage timouride: Iran-Asie centrale-Inde  XVe–XVIIIe siècles, pp. 105–128, 111–117; Rizvi, Religious and Intellectual History of the Mus lims in Akbar’s Reign, pp. 355–356, 366–369.

48 In the administrative manual (dastūr al-‘amal) issued by Akbar in 1594, the Nasirean  Ethics was included in the standard readings for Mughal officials—see Mukātabāt-i-‘Allāmī  (Inshā’i Abu’l Faẓl) Daftar I: Letters of the Emperor Akbar in English Translation, ed. Mansura  Haidar (New Delhi: M. Manoharlal Publishers, 1998), p. 79.

49  Abū’l-Faẓl ‘Allāmī, Āīn-i Akbarī, trans. Henry Blochmann, 2nd ed. (Calcutta: Asi atic Society of Bengal, 1927), p. 2.

46 Practical Philosophy of the Muhammadan People, pp. 324–325; Deen, The English Trans lation of the Akhlak-i-Jalali, pp. 164–165.

47 Alam, The Languages of Political Islam, p. 50; Alam, “State Building under the  Mughals: Religion, Culture and Politics,” in L’Héritage timouride: Iran-Asie centrale-Inde  XVe–XVIIIe siècles, pp. 105–128, 111–117; Rizvi, Religious and Intellectual History of the Mus lims in Akbar’s Reign, pp. 355–356, 366–369.

48 In the administrative manual (dastūr al-‘amal) issued by Akbar in 1594, the Nasirean  Ethics was included in the standard readings for Mughal officials—see Mukātabāt-i-‘Allāmī  (Inshā’i Abu’l Faẓl) Daftar I: Letters of the Emperor Akbar in English Translation, ed. Mansura  Haidar (New Delhi: M. Manoharlal Publishers, 1998), p. 79.

49  Abū’l-Faẓl ‘Allāmī, Āīn-i Akbarī, trans. Henry Blochmann, 2nd ed. (Calcutta: Asi atic Society of Bengal, 1927), p. 2.

50  Muḥammad Bāqir Najm-i Sānī, Advice on the Art of Governance: An Indo-Islamic Mir ror for Princes (Mau’iẓah-i Jahāngīrī), ed. and trans. Sajida S. Alvi (Albany: State University  of New York Press, 1989), Persian text p. 147/English trans. p. 45.

51 Ḥujjat Allāh al-Bālighah, 1:44; Hermansen, The Conclusive Argument from God, pp.  129–130. See also Waliyullah, Al-Budūr al-Bāzighah, pp. 85–86; Baljon, Full Moon Appearing  on the Horizon, pp. 91–93.

52 Waliyullah, Al-Budūr al-Bāzighah, pp. 49–50; Baljon, Full Moon Appearing on the  Horizon, p. 58.

53 Ḥujjat Allāh al-Bālighah, 1:49; Hermansen, The Conclusive Argument from God, p. 139.

54 For further discussion on the use of medical metaphors in early modern Islamic  political writing, see Vasileios Syros, “Galenic Medicine and Domestic Stability in Early  Modern Florence and Islamic Empires,” Journal of Early Modern History 17, no. 1 (2013,  forthcoming).

55 Alam, The Languages of Political Islam, pp. 47, 57–58, 61, 140; A. J. Halepota, Philoso phy of Shah Waliullah (Lahore: Sind Sagar Academy, [197-?]), p. 166.

56 Waliyullah, Al-Budūr al-Bāzighah, pp. 49–50; Baljon, Full Moon Appearing on the  Horizon, p. 58. See also Alam, The Languages of Political Islam, p. 173. 57 Antony Black, The West and Islam: Religion and Political Thought in World History  (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008), pp. 58, 104–105; Black, The History of Islamic  Political Thought: From the Prophet to the Present (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press;  New York: Routledge, 2001), pp. 53–54, 111.

58 My discussion of the “circle of justice” is based on the following studies by Linda T.  Darling: “Islamic Empires, the Ottoman Empire and the Circle of Justice,” in Constitutional  Politics in the Middle East: With Special Reference to Turkey, Iraq, Iran and Afghanistan, ed.  Saïd Amir Arjomand (Oxford: Hart Publishing, 2008), pp. 11–32; “Political Change and  Political Discourse in the Early Modern Mediterranean World,” Journal of Interdisciplinary  History 38 (2008): 505–531; “Medieval Egyptian Society and the Concept of the Circle of  Justice,” Mamlūk Studies Review 10 (2006): 1–17; “‘Do Justice, Do Justice, For That Is Para

dise’: Middle Eastern Advice for Indian Muslim Rulers,” Comparative Studies of South Asia,  Africa and the Middle East 22 (2002): 3–19; as well as Jennifer A. London, “The ‘Circle of  Justice,’” History of Political Thought 32 (2011): 425–447; Maria E. Subtelny, Le monde est un  jardin: Aspects de l’histoire culturelle de l’Iran médiéval (Paris: Association pour l’avancement  des études iraniennes, 2002), chap. “Le cercle de justice: l’éthique dans le gouvernement,”  pp. 53–76; Joseph Sadan, “A ‘Closed-Circuit’ Saying on Practical Justice,” Jerusalem Studies  in Arabic and Islam 10 (1987): 325–341; Ann K. S. Lambton, “Justice in the Medieval Per

sian Theory of Kingship,” Studia Islamica 17 (1962): 91–119, repr. in Lambton, Theory and  Practice in Medieval Persian Government (London: Variorum, 1980), no. 4.

59  Ihsān ‘Abbās, ed., ‘Ahd Ardashīr (Beirut: Dār al-Ṣādir, 1967), p. 98; Mario Grignaschi,  “Quelques spécimens de la littérature sassanide conservés dans les bibliothèques d’Istanbul,”  Journal Asiatique 254 (1966): 1–142, 46–90. For another set of maxims on rulership that  bears the title Ā‘īn-i Ardashīr and has been ascribed to Ardashīr, see Grignaschi, “Quelques  spécimens de la littérature sassanide,” pp. 91–133.

60  Naṣīr al-Ṭūsī, Akhlāq-i Nāṣirī, p. 303; The Nasirean Ethics, p. 230.61 Practical Philosophy of the Muhammadan People, pp. 388–390; Deen, The English Trans lation of Akhlak-i-Jalali, pp. 201–203. See also Black, The History of Islamic Political Thought, p. 185.

62 Practical Philosophy of the Muhammadan People, pp. 384–385; Deen, The English Trans lation of Akhlak-i-Jalali, pp. 199–200.

63 Practical Philosophy of the Muhammadan People, p. 388; Deen, The English Translation  of Akhlak-i-Jalali, p. 201.

64 Practical Philosophy of the Muhammadan People, pp. 325–326, 383–384; Deen, The  English Translation of Akhlak-i-Jalali, pp. 165, 199.

65 Mohammad Habib and Afsar U. S. Khan, The Political Theory of the Delhi Sultanate (Including a Translation of Ziauddin Barani’s Fatāwā-i Jahāndārī, Circa, 1358–9 a.d.) (Alla habad: Kitab Mahal, [1961]), pp. 38, 97. On Baranī’s ideas on social organization, see also  Iqtidar A. Khan, “Medieval Indian Notions of Secular Statecraft in Retrospect,” Social Sci entist 14 (1986): 3–15, 6–7. Baranī’s views on price control are discussed in Najaf Haider,  “Justice and Political Authority in Medieval Indian Islam,” in Justice: Political, Social, Juridi cal, ed. Rajeev Bhargava et al. (New Delhi: SAGE Publications, 2006), pp. 75–93; Irfan  Habib, “Ziya Barani’s Vision of the State,” Medieval History Journal 2 (1999): 19–36; and  Habib,  “The  Price Regulations  of  ‘Alā’  uddīn Khaljī—A  Defence  of  Ziā’  Baranī,’ Indian  Economic and Social History Review 21 (1984): 393–414.

66  Abū’l-Faẓl ‘Allāmī, Āīn-i Akbarī, p. 2. On Abū’l-Faẓl’s use of medical analogies, see  also the discussion in Peter Hardy, “Abul Fazl’s Portrait of the Perfect Padshah: A Political  Philosophy for Mughal India—or a Personal Puff for a Pal,” in Islam in India: Studies and  Commentaries, vol. 2, Religion and Religious Education, ed. Christian W. Troll (New Delhi:  Vikas Pub. House, 1985), pp. 114–137, 133–135.

67 Ḥujjat Allāh al-Bālighah, 1:44; Hermansen, The Conclusive Argument from God, pp.  129–130; Waliyullah, Al-Budūr al-Bāzighah, pp. 85–86; Baljon, Full Moon Appearing on  the Horizon, pp. 91–93. For earlier Indo-Islamic ideas on emergencies, see Vasileios Syros,  “Indian  Emergencies:  Baranī’s  Fatāwā-i Jahāndārī, the Diseases of the Body Politic, and  Machiavelli’s accidenti,” Philosophy East and West 62, no. 4 (2012): 545–573.

68 Ḥujjat Allāh al-Bālighah, 1:44–45; Hermansen, The Conclusive Argument from God, pp. 130–131.

69 Ḥujjat Allāh al-Bālighah, 1:40; Hermansen, The Conclusive Argument from God, p.  131.

70 Khalid A. Nizami, ed., Shāh Valī Dihlavī ke siyāsī maktūbāt (Delhi: Nadvat al-Musan nifin, 1969), pp. 102–105.

71 Nizami, Shāh Valī Dihlavī ke siyāsī maktūbāt, pp. 15, 52. See also Jalbani, Teachings of  Shāh Walīullah of Delhi, pp. 114–117.

72 On Mughal “decline,” see, e.g., Douglas E. Streusand, Islamic Gunpowder Empires:  Otto mans, Safavids, and Mughals (Boulder, Colo.: Westview Press, 2011), pp. 283–287;  Muzaf far Alam, The Crisis of Empire in Mughal North India: Awadh and the Punjab, 1707–48 (Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1986; repr., 1997); Andrea Hintze, The Mughal Empire and  Its Decline: An Interpretation of the Sources of Social Power (Aldershot: Ashgate, 1997); Karen  Leonard, “The ‘Great Firm’ Theory of the Decline of the Mughal Empire,” Comparative  Studies in Society and History 21 (1979): 151–167; John F. Richards, “The Imperial Crisis in  the Deccan,” Journal of Asian Studies 35 (1976): 236–256, repr. in Richards, Power, Adminis

tration and Finance in Mughal India (Aldershot: Variorum, 1993), no. 12; M. Athar Ali, “The  Passing of Empire: The Mughal Case,” Modern Asian Studies 9 (1975): 385–396, repr. in Ali,  Mughal India: Studies in Polity, Ideas, Society, and Culture (New Delhi: Oxford University  Press, 2006), pp. 337–349; Saiyid A. A. Rizvi, “The Breakdown of Traditional Society,” in

The Cambridge History of Islam, vol. 2A, The Indian Sub-continent, South-East Asia, Africa and  the Muslim West, ed. Peter M. Holt et al. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970;  repr., 1980), pp. 67–96.

73 See, in general, Catherine B. Asher and Cynthia Talbot, India before Europe (Cam bridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006), chap. “Challenging Central Authority, 1650– 1750,” pp. 225–255.

74 The following account is based on Islahi, “Shah Wali Allah’s Concept of Al-Irtifaqat  (Stages of Socio-Economic Development),” pp. 48–49; Fazl-e-Mahmud Asiri, “Shah Wali  Allah as a Politician,” Islamic Literature 7 (1955): 35–41.

75  For a similar interpretation, see A. J. Halepota, “Shāh Waliyullāh and Iqbāl, the Phi losophers of Modern Age,” Islamic Studies 13 (1974): 225–233, repr. in SWRPT, pp. 649–656;  Halepota, “Affinity of Iqbāl with Shāh Walī Allāh,” Iqbal Review 15 (1974): 65–72; Fazlur  Rahman, “The Thinker of Crisis Shah Waliy-Ullah,” Pakistan Quarterly (1956): 44–48.

76  Shāh Walī Allāh’s political activities are discussed in A. Sattar Khan and Zulfiqar  Anwar, “The Movement of Shah Waliullah and Its Political Impact,” Journal of the Research  Society of Pakistan 32, no. 4 (1995): 13–23; Freeland Abbott, “The Decline of the Mughal  Empire and Shah Waliullah,” Muslim World 52 (1962): 115–123; Aziz Ahmad, “Political  and Religious  Ideas  of  Shāh Walī-Ullāh  of Delhi,” Muslim World 52 (1962): 22–30, esp.  28–30, partly repr. in Ahmad, Studies in Islamic Culture in the Indian Environment (Oxford:  Clarendon Press, 1964), pp. 201–209;  Franco  Coslovi,  “Osservazioni  sul  ruolo  di  ‘Šāh  Walīullāh Dihlawī’ e ‘Šāh ‘Abd al-‘Azīz’ nella ‘Naqšbandiyya’ Indiana,” Annali dell’ Istituto  Orientale di Napoli, n.s., 29 (1979): 73–84, esp. 73–81; Irfan M. Habib, “The Political Role  of Shaikh Ahmad Sirhindi and Shah Waliullah,” in Indian History Congress: Proceedings of  the Twenty-third Session Aligarh—1960, pt. I (Calcutta, 1961), pp. 209–223; Sh. Muhammad  Ikram, “Shah Waliullah (I) (Life and Achievements in the Religious Sphere),” in A History  of the Freedom Movement (Being the Story of Muslim Struggle for the Freedom of Hind-Pakistan,  1707–1947), vol. 1, 1707–1831 (Karachi: Pakistan Historical Society, 1957), pp. 491–511;  Khaliq A. Nizami, “Shah Waliullah (II) (His Work in the Political Field),” in A History of  the Freedom Movement, 1:512–541; Nizami, “Shah Wali-Ullah Dehlavi and Indian Politics  in the 18th Century,” Islamic Culture 25 (1951): 133–145, repr. in SWRPT, pp. 143–157;  ‘Ubaidullah Sindhi, Shah Wali Allah and His Political Movement [in Urdu] (Lahore: Sindh  Sagar Akademy, 1952).

77 On the history of the order, see Butrus Abu-Manneh, The Naqshbandiyya-Khâlidiyya  Sufi Order (Paris: Librairie d’Amérique et d’Orient, 2008); Itzchak Weismann, The Naqsh bandiyya: Orthodoxy and Activism in a Worldwide Sufi Tradition (London: Routledge, 2007); Sajida  S.  Alvi,  “The  Naqshbandī  Mujaddidī  Sufi  Order’s  Ascendancy  in  Central  Asia  through the Eyes of Its Masters and Disciples (1010s–1200s/1600s–1800s),” in Reason and  Inspiration in Islam: Theology,Philosophy and Mysticism in Muslim Thought, ed. Todd Lawson  (London: I. B. Tauris, 2005), pp. 418–431; Elisabeth Özdalga, ed., Naqshbandis in Western  and Central Asia: Change and Continuity (Istanbul: Svenska Forskningsinstitutet Istanbul,  1999); Marc Gaborieau et al., eds., Naqshbandis: Cheminements et situation actuelle d’un ordre  mystique musulman (Istanbul: Isis, 1990); Richard Foltz,  “The Central Asian Naqshbandī  Connections of the Mughal Emperors,” Journal of Islamic Studies 7 (1996): 229–239; Hamid  Algar, “The Naqshbandi Order: A Preliminary Survey of Its History and Significance,” Stu dia Islamica 44 (1976): 123–152. A number of seminal essays dealing with Sufi influences on  medieval Indian society have been reprinted in Raziuddin Aquil, ed., Sufism and Society in  Medieval India (New Delhi: Oxford University Press, 2010). Consult also Raziuddin Aquil’s  introduction to Sufism and Society, pp. ix–xxiv.

78 Jürgen Paul, Die politische und soziale Bedeutung der Naqšbandiyya in Mittelasien im  15. Jahrhundert (Berlin: W. de Gruyter, 1991), chap. “Politische Tätigkeit,” pp. 208–244;  and Jo-Ann Gross, “Khoja Ahrar: A Study of the Perceptions of Religious Power and Pres tige in the Late Timurid Period” (PhD diss., New York University, 1982). The role of the  Naqshbandi order in Mughal political life is discussed in Muzaffar Alam, “The Mughals,  the Sufi Shaikhs and the Formation of the Akbari Dispensation,” Modern Asian Studies 43 (2009): 135–174; David W. Damrel, “The ‘Naqshbandī Reaction’ Reconsidered,” in Beyond  Turk and Hindu: Rethinking Religious Identities in Islamicate South Asia, ed. David Gilmar tin and Bruce B. Lawrence (Gainesville: University Press of Florida, 2000), pp. 176–198;  Arthur F. Buehler, Sufi Heirs of the Prophet: The Indian Naqshbandiyya and the Rise of the  Mediating Sufi Shaykh (Columbia: University of South Carolina Press, 1998); Muhammad  Farman, “Shaikh Ahmad Sirhindi,” in A History of Muslim Philosophy, ed. Mian M. Sharif  (Wiesbaden: O. Harrassowitz, 1966), 2:873–883; Khaliq A. Nizami, “Naqshbandi Influence  on Mughal Rulers and Politics,” Islamic Culture 39 (1965): 41–52; Rizvi, Muslim Revivalist  Movements in Northern India in the Sixteenth and Seventeenth Centuries, “The Naqshbandis,”  pp. 176–201; and Wilfred Cantwell Smith, “The ‘ulamā’ in Indian Politics,” in Politics and  Society in India, ed. Cyril H. Philips (London: Allen and Unwin, 1963), pp. 39–51.

79 The Arabic term ‘ajam generally refers to a foreigner (non-Arab), but is often used to  designate an Iranian/Persian as is the case with Shāh Walī Allāh’s discussion of Sassanian  political history. See, in general, Mohamad Tavakoli-Targhi, “Contested Memories of Pre Islamic Iran,” Medieval History Journal 2 (1999): 245–275.

80 Ḥujjat Allāh al-Bālighah, 1:105; Hermansen, The Conclusive Argument from God, p. 306. For references to Byzantine and Sassanian political history and royal practices in  earlier Indo-Islamic political literature, consider, e.g., Afsar Afzal ud-din, “The Fatawa-i Jahandari of Zia ud-din Barni, Translation with Introduction and Notes” (PhD diss., School  of Oriental and African Studies, 1955), pp. 107, 152–153, 417–418, 424–429, 450–451,  466, 484–491.

81 Ḥujjat Allāh al-Bālighah, 1:105–106; Hermansen, The Conclusive Argument from God, pp. 306–307.

82 Byzantine views on the Mongols and the emergence of the Islamic empires of central  Asia are discussed in, e.g., Antonis K. Petrides, “Georgios Pachymeres between Ethnog raphy and Narrative: Συγγραφικαὶ Ἱστορίαι 3.3–5,” Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies 49 (2009): 141–164, esp. 295–296, 316–317; Nikolaos Nikoloudes, “Byzantine Historians on  the Wars of Timur,” Journal of Oriental and African Studies 8 (1996): 83–94; Alexis G. K. [C.]  Savvides, “The Knowledge of the Byzantines about the Turkish-Speaking World of Asia,  the Balkans and Central Europe through Name Giving,” in Communication in Byzantium, ed. Nikos G. Moschonas (Athens: National Hellenic Research Foundation/Institute for  Byzantine Research, 1993), pp. 711–727 [both in Greek]; Savvides, Byzantium in the Near  East: Its Relations with the Seljuk Sultanate of Rum in Asia Minor, the Armenians of Cilicia and  the Mongols, A.D. c. 1192–1237 (Thessalonike: Center for Byzantine Studies/University of  Thessaloniki, 1981); John W. Barker, Manuel II Palaeologus (1391–1425): A Study in Late  Byzantine Statesmanship (New Brunswick, N.J.: Rutgers University Press, 1969), Appendix  XVIII: “Byzantine Relations with Timur,” pp. 504–509. Also of note are John S. Langdon,  “Byzantium’s Initial Encounter with the Chinggisids: An Introduction to the Byzantino Mongolica,” Viator 29 (1998): 95–139; Angeliki E. Laiou, “On Political Geography: The  Black Sea of Pachymeres,” in The Making of Byzantine History, ed. Roderick Beaton and  Charlotte Roueché (Aldershot: Variorum, 1993), pp. 94–121, 112–121; Bruce G. Lippard,  “The Mongols and Byzantium, 1243–1341” (PhD diss., Indiana University, 1983); Maria Mathilde Alexandrescu-Dersca, La campagne de Timur en Anatolie (1402) (Bucharest:  Monitorul Oficial şi Imprimeriile Statului, Imprimeria Naţionalǎ, 1942; 2nd ed., London:  Variorum Reprints, 1977); Andreas Graf, “Die Tataren im Spiegel der byzantinischen Lit eratur,” in Jubilee Volume in Honour of Prof. Bernhard Heller on the Occasion of His Seventieth  Birthday, ed. Alexander Scheiber (Budapest, 1941), pp. 77–85; Fedor I. Uspensky, “Byz antine Historians on the Mongols and the Egyptian Mamluks,” Vizantiysky Vremmenik 24 (1923–1926): 1–16 (in Russian); Ottokar Intze, “Tamerlan und Bajazet in den Literaturen  des Abendlandes” (Erlangen: E. Th. Jacob, 1912), pp. 5–9. On Byzantine perceptions of  Islam and the Arabs, see Wolfram Brandes, “Der frühe Islam in der byzantinischen Histo riographie: Anmerkungen zur Quellenproblematik der Chronographia des Theophanes,” in  Jenseits der Grenzen: Beiträge zur spätantiken und frühmittelalterlichen Geschichtsschreibung, ed. Andreas Goltz et al. (Berlin: W. de Gruyter, 2009), pp. 313–343; Elizabeth M. Jef freys, “The Image of the Arabs in Byzantine Literature,” in The 17th International Byzantine  Congress: Major Papers (New Rochelle, N.Y.: A. D. Caratzas, 1986), pp. 305–323; Spe ros Vryonis Jr.,“Byzantine Attitudes toward Islam during the Late Middle Ages,” Greek,  Roman and Byzantine Studies 12 (1971): 263–286, repr. in Vryonis, Studies on Byzantium,  Seljuks, and Ottomans: Reprinted Studies (Malibu: Undena Publications, 1981), no. 8; Alain  Ducellier, “Mentalité historique et realités politiques: L’Islam et les Musulmans vus par les  Byzantins du XIIIème siècle,” Byzantinische Forschungen 4 (1972): 31–63; John Meyendorff,  “Byzantine Views of Islam,” Dumbarton Oaks Papers 18 (1964): 114–132; and Wolfgang  Eichner, “Die Nachrichten über den Islam bei den Byzantinern,” Islam 23 (1936): 133–162 and 197–244.

83 For medieval Islamic ideas on kingship, see, e.g., Anne F. Broadbridge, Kingship and  Ideology in the Islamic and Mongol Worlds (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008);  Aziz al-Azmeh, Muslim Kingship: Power and the Sacred in Muslim, Christian, and Pagan Polities  (London: I. B. Tauris, 1997); Saiyid A. A. Rizvi, “Kingship in Islam: Islamic Universalism  through the Caliphate,” in Patterns of Kingship and Authority in Traditional Asia, ed. Ian  Mabbett (London: Croom Helm, 1985), pp. 108–130; Rizvi, “Kingship in Islam: A Histori

cal Analysis,” in Kingship in Asia and Early America, ed. Arthur L. Basham (Mexico City:  El Colegio de México, 1981), pp. 29–82; Tilman Nagel, Staat und Glaubensgemeinschaft im  Islam: Geschichte der politischen Ordnungsvorstellungen der Muslime, 2 vols. (Zurich: Arte mis, 1981); Roy P. Mottahedeh, “Some Attitudes towards Monarchy and Absolutism in the  Eastern Islamic World of the Eleventh and Twelfth Centuries A.D.,” Israel Oriental Studies 10 (1980): 86–91.

84 For further discussion, see the following studies by Bernard Lewis: The Political Lan guage of Islam (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1988), pp. 55, 93, 96–97; “Malik,”  Cahiers de Tunisie 35 (1987): 101–109; “Usurpers and Tyrants: Notes on Some Islamic  Terms,” in Logos Islamikos, ed. Roger M. Savory and Dionisius A. Agius (Toronto: Pontifical  Institute of Mediaeval Studies, 1984), pp. 259–267, both repr. in Lewis, Political Words and  Ideas in Islam (Princeton, N.J.: M. Wiener Publishers, 2008), pp. 77–86 and 49–58, respec tively. Note also Fred Halliday, “Monarchies in the Middle East: A Concluding Appraisal,”  in Middle East Monarchies: The Challenge of Modernity, ed. Joseph Kostiner (Boulder, Colo.:  Lynne Rienner Publishers, 2000), pp. 289–303, 292–293; Ami Ayalon, Language and Change  in the Arab Middle East: The Evolution of Modern Political Discourse (New York: Oxford Uni versity Press, 1987), chap. “Sultans, Kings, Emperors,” pp. 29–42; Ayalon, “Malik in Modern  Middle Eastern Titulature,” Die Welt des Islams 23/24 (1984): 306–319, esp. 307–312; Herib ert Busse, “Herrschertypen im Koran,” in Die Islamische Welt zwischen Mittelalter und Neuzeit, ed. Ulrich Haarmann und Peter Bachmann (Wiesbaden: F. Steiner, 1979), pp. 56–80, esp.  67–71; Arent J. Wensinck-[Georges Vajda], s.v. “Fir‛awn,” in Encyclopedia of Islam, new  ed. (Leiden: E. J. Brill; London: Luzac, 1965), vol. 2, pt. 2: 917–918. Medieval Islamic per ceptions of ancient Egypt are surveyed in Konrad Hirschler, “The ‘Pharaoh’ Anecdote in  Pre-Modern Arabic Historiography,” Journal of Arabic and Islamic Studies 10 (2010): 45–74;  Ulrich Haarmann, “Medieval Muslim Perceptions of Pharaonic Egypt,” in Ancient Egyptian  Literature: History and Forms, ed. Antonio Loprieno (Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1996), pp. 605–627;  Haarmann, “Das pharaonische Ägypten bei islamischen Autoren des Mittelalters,” in Zum  Bild Ägyptens im Mittelalter und in der Renaissance, ed. Erik Hornung (Freiburg [i. Ü.]: Uni versitätsverlag Freiburg Schweiz, 1990), pp. 29–58; Hans R. Roemer, “Der Islam und das  Erbe der Pharaonen: Neuere Erkenntnisse zu einem alten Thema,” in Ägypten—Dauer und  Wandel (Mainz am Rhein: P. v. Zabern, 1985), pp. 123–129; Michael Cook, “Pharaonic  History in Medieval Egypt,” Studia Islamica 57 (1983): 67–103. Consider also Adam Silver stein, “The Qur’ānic Pharaoh,” in New Pespectives on the Qur’ān: The Qur’ān in Its Historical  Context 2, ed. Gabriel Said Reynolds (London: Routledge, 2011), pp. 467–477; and Reuven  Firestone, “Pharaoh,” in Encyclopaedia of the Qur’ān, ed. Jane D. McAuliffe (Leiden: Brill,  2004), 4:66–68. For a general treatment of medieval Islamic views of the pre-Islamic era, see  Monika Springberg-Hinsen, Die Zeit vor dem Islam in arabischen Universalgeschichten des 9.  und 12. Jahrhunderts (Würzburg: Echter; Altenberge: Telos-Verlag, 1989).

85 Okasha El-Daly, Egyptology: The Missing Millennium: Ancient Egypt in Medieval Arabic  Writings (London: UCL Press, 2005), pp. 122–126.

86 On the etymology and use of the term rūm and its derivatives in medieval Arabic  writing, see Nadia Maria El Cheikh, Byzantium Viewed by the Arabs (Cambridge, Mass.:  Center for Middle Eastern Studies of Harvard University, 2004), pp. 21–33; as well as Niko lai Serikoff, “Rūmī and yūnānī: Towards the Understanding of the Greek language in the  Medieval Muslim World,” in East and West in the Crusader States: Context—Contacts—Con frontations, ed. Krijnie Ciggaar et al. (Leuven: Peeters, 1996), pp. 169–194, esp. 172–183.

87 El Cheikh, Byzantium Viewed by the Arabs, pp. 86–87. On Byzantium’s image in  medieval Islam and Byzantine-Arab relations, see in addition to El Cheikh: Olof Heilo,  “Seeing Eye to Eye: Islamic Universalism in the Roman and Byzantine Worlds, 7th to 10th  Centuries” (diss., University of Vienna, 2010); Ulrike Koenen and Martina Müller-Wiener,  eds., Grenzgänge im östlichen Mittelmeerraum: Byzanz und die islamische Welt vom 9. bis 13.  Jahrhundert (Wiesdaben: Reichert Verlag, 2008); Michael Bonner, ed., Arab-Byzantine Rela

tions in Early Islamic Times (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2004); Ahmad M. H. Shboul, “Arab Islamic  Perceptions of Byzantine Religion and Culture,” in Muslim Perceptions of Other Religions:  A Historical Survey, ed. Jacques Waardenburg (New York: Oxford University Press, 1999),  pp. 122–135; Shboul, “Arab Attitudes towards Byzantium: Official, Learned, Popular,” in  ΚΑΘΗΓΗΤΡΙΑ: Essays Presented to Joan Hussey for her 80th Birthday (Camberley, Sur

rey: Porphyrogenitus, 1988), pp. 111–128; and Speros Vryonis Jr., “Byzantium and Islam,  Seven–Seventeenth Century,” East European Quarterly 11 (1968): 205–240, repr. in Vry onis, Byzan tium: Its Internal History and Relations with the Muslim World: Collected Studies  (London: Variorum Reprints, 1971), no. 9.

88 El Cheikh, Byzantium Viewed by the Arabs, p. 70; David Cook, “Muslim Apocalyptic  and Jihād,” Jerusalem Studies in Arabic and Islam 20 (1996): 66–104, esp. 83–96. 89  Ḥasan  al-Sandūbī,  ed.,  Rasāʾil al-Jāḥiz: Wa-hiya rasāʾil muntaqāt min kutub lil-Jāḥiẓ lam tunshar qabl al-ān (Cairo: Yuṭlab min al-maktabah al-Tijārīyah al-Kubra, 1933), p. 117;

Charles Pellat, “La Nâbita de Djâhiz: Un document important pour l’histoire politico-reli gieuse de l’Islâm,” Annales de l’Institut d’Études Orientales 10 (1952): 302–325, 314. See also  El Cheikh, Byzantium Viewed by the Arabs, p. 87; Lewis, The Political Language of Islam, p. 55.

90  Abī al-Qāsim ibn Ḥawqal al-Naṣībī, Kītāb ṣūrat al-ard (Beirut: Manshurat Dar Mak tabat al-Hayāh, [1963]), p. 181; Ibn Hauqal, Configuration de la terre (Kitab Surat al-ard), trans. Johannes H. Kramers and G. Wiet (Paris: G. P. Maisonneuve et Larose, 1964), 1:194. 91 El Cheikh, Byzantium Viewed by the Arabs, p. 197.

92 Ibn Khaldûn, The Muqaddimah: An Introduction to History, trans. Franz Rosenthal  (New York: Pantheon Books, 1958), 2:50.

93  Averroès (Ibn Rušd), Commentaire moyen à la Rhétorique d’Aristote, ed. and French  trans. Maroun Aouad (Paris: Vrin, 2002), 2:70. For further discussion, see Commentaire  moyen à la Rhétorique, 3:35; as well as Rémi Brague, The Legend of the Middle Ages: Philosophi cal Explorations of Medieval Christianity, Judaism, and Islam, trans. from the French Lydia G.  Cochrane (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2009), pp. 122–123.

94 General accounts of the decline of the Byzantine Empire include Jonathan Harris,  The End of Byzantium (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 2010); John F. Haldon,  “The Byzantine Empire,” in The Dynamics of Ancient Empires: State Power from Assyria to  Byzantium, ed. Ian Morris and Walter Scheidel (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), pp.  205–254; Motyl, Imperial Ends, pp. 59–61; Franz Georg Maier, “Byzanz: Selbstbehauptung  und Zerfall einer Großmacht,” in Das Verdämmern der Macht: Vom Untergang großer Reiche, ed. Richard Lorenz (Frankfurt a. M.: Fischer Taschenbuch Verlag, 2000), pp. 44–59; Peter  Schreiner, “Schein und Sein: Überlegungen zu den Ursachen des Untergangs des byzan

tinischen Reiches,” Historische Zeitschrift 266 (1998): 625–647; Donald M. Nicol: “Der Fall  von Byzanz,” in Das Ende der Weltreiche: Von den Persern bis zur Sowjetunion, ed. Alexander  Demandt (Munich: C. H. Beck, 1997), pp. 61–73; Nicol, “Der Niedergang von Byzanz,”  in Byzanz, ed. Franz G. Maier (Frankfurt a. M.: Fischer, 1973; repr., Augsburg: Weltbild

Verl., 1998), pp. 348–406; Nicol, Church and Society in the Last Centuries of Byzan tium:  The Birkbeck Lectures, 1977 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979; repr., 1993);  Klaus-Peter Matschke, “Der Untergang einer Großmacht. Thesen und Hypothesen zur Stel lung von Byzanz in einer vergleichenden Niedergangsgeschichte von Staaten und Gesell schaften,” Zeitschrift für Geschichtswissenschaft 37 (1989): 890–904; Franz Tinnefeld, “Zur  Krise des Spätmittelalters in Byzanz,” in Europa 1400: Die Krise des Spätmittelalters, ed. Fer dinand Seibt and Winfried Eberhard (Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta, 1984), pp. 284–294; as well as  Ivan Dujčev, “Die Krise der spätbyzantinischen Gesellschaft und die türkische Eroberung  des 14. Jahrhunderts,” Jahrbücher für Geschichte Osteuropas 21 (1973): 481–492; Peter Cha ranis, “Economic Factors in the Decline of the Byzantine Empire,” Journal of Economic His tory 13 (1953): 412–424, repr. in Charanis, Social, Economic and Political Life in the Byzantine  Empire, no. 9; Dionysios A. Zakythinos, Crise monétaire et crise économique à Byzance du XIIIe au XVe siècle (Athens: L’Hellénisme contemporain, 1948); Rodolphe Guilland, “Vénalité  et favoritisme à Byzance,” Revue des Études Byzantines 10 (1952): 35–46; and, in general,  Warren Treadgold, A History of the Byzantine State and Society (Stanford, Calif.: Stanford  University Press, 1997); Donald M. Nicol, The Last Centuries of Byzantium, 1261–1453, 2nd ed. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993). A detailed discussion of the role of  the Byzantine Empire in Mediterranean trade appears in Angeliki E. Laiou [-Thomadakis],  “The Byzantine Economy in the Mediterranean Trade System; Thirteenth–Fifteenth Cen turies,” Dumbarton Oaks Papers 34–35 (1980/81): 177–222, repr. in Laiou, Gender, Society  and Economic Life in Byzantium (Hampshire: Variorum, 1992), no. 7. Consider also Lazaros  Houmanidis, Byzantine Commerce, the Impact on It of Arab Expansion and of the Rise of the  Italian Cities (Thessalonike, 1968).

95 I am grateful to Professor Anthony Kaldellis for discussions on this point.

96 Hans Thurn, ed., Ioannis Scylitzae Synopsis historiarum (Berlin: De Gruyter, 1973),  pp. 273–274; John Skylitzes, A Synopsis of Byzantine History, 811–1057, trans. John Wortley  (Cambridge: Cambridge University Presss, 2010), pp. 262–264. Skylitzes’s views on Pho kas’s reign are discussed in Eirene-Sophia Kiapidou, John Skylitzes’ Synopsis of Histories and  Its Sources (811–1057): A Contribution to Byzantine Historiography during the 11th Century [in  Greek] (Athens: Kanakes, 2010), pp. 345–359. See, in general, also Rosemary Morris, “The  Two Faces of Nikephoros Phokas,” Byzantine and Modern Greek Studies 12 (1988): 83–115.  On the tetarteron in particular, consult Cécile Morrisson, “Monnayage et monnaies,” in  Économie et société à Byzance (VIIIe–XIIe siècle): Textes et documents, ed. Sophie Métivier  (Paris: Publications de la Sorbonne, 2007), pp. 157–165, 163; Michael F. Hendy, Studies in  the Byzantine Monetary Economy, c. 300–1450 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,  1985), pp. 506–508; Hendy, “Light Weight Solidi, Tetartera, and The Book of the Prefect,”  Byzantinische Zeitschrift 65 (1972): 57–80, repr. in Hendy, The Economy, Fiscal Administra

tion and Coinage of Byzantium (Northampton: Variorum Reprints, 1989), no. 9; Hélène  Ahrweiler[-Glykatzi], “Nouvelle hypothèse sur le tétartèron d’or et la politique monétaire  de Nicéphore Phocas,” Zbornik Radova Vizantološkog Instituta 8 (1963): 1–9, repr. in Ahrwei ler, Etudes sur les structures administratives et sociales de Byzance (London: Variorum Reprints,  1971), no. 3. Gustave Schlumberger’s Un empereur byzantin au dixième siècle, Nicéphore Pho cas (Paris: Librairie de Firmin-Didot et cie, 1890) is an older study, but still valuable for its  insights into Byzatine-Arab relations during Phokas’s reign.

97 An extensive treatment of critiques of Byzantine leadership as articulated in Byz antine historiography in the period between the sixth and thirteenth centuries appears in  Franz Hermann Tinnefeld, Kategorien der Kaiserkritik in der byzantinischen Historiographie von  Prokop bis Niketas Choniates (Munich: W. Fink, 1971).

98 For further discussion, see Paul J. Alexander, “The Strength of Empire and Capital as  Seen through Byzantine Eyes,” Speculum 37 (1962): 339–357, 356–357, repr. in Alexander,  Religious and Political History and Thought in the Byzantine Empire (London: Variorum, 1978),  no. 3. The process of economic decline in twelfth-century Byzantium has been studied by  Alan Harvey, “Economy,” in Palgrave Advances in Byzantine History, ed. Jonathan Harris  (Lon don: Palgrave Macmillan, 2005), pp. 83–99, esp. 91–96; Harvey, Economic Expansion in  the Byzantine Empire 900–1200 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990); Michael F.  Hendy, “Byzantium, 1081–1204: An Economic Reappraisal,” Transactions of The Royal His torical Society, ser. 5, 20 (1970): 31–52, repr. in Hendy, The Economy, Fiscal Administration  and Coinage of Byzantium, no. 2. For other aspects of the decay of Byzantine power during  the same period, see Vassiliki N. Vlyssidou, ed., The Empire in Crisis (?): Byzantium in the  11th Century (1025–1081) (Athens: National Hellenic Research Foundation/Institute for  Byzantine Research, 2003); Judith Herrin, “The Collapse of the Byzantine Empire in the  Twelfth Century: A Study of Medieval Economy,” University of Birmingham Historical Jour

nal 12 (1970): 188–203; Speros Vryonis Jr., “Byzantium: The Social Basis of Decline in the  Eleventh Century,” Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies 2 (1959): 157–175, repr. in Vryonis,  Byzantium: Its Internal History and Relations with the Muslim World, no. 2. On the erosion of  Byzantine identity and the spread of Islam in Asia Minor, see Speros Vryonis Jr., The Decline  of Medieval Hellenism in Asia Minor and the Process of Islamization from the Eleventh through  the Fifteenth Century (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1971; repr., 1986); and, in  general, Manzikert to Lepanto: The Byzantine World and the Turks 1071–1571 [= Byzantinische  Forschungen 16 (1991)], ed. Anthony Bryer and Michael Ursinus (Amsterdam: A. M. Hak

kert, 1991); Alexis G. Savvides, The Turks and Byzantium, vol. 1, Pre-Ottoman Tribes in Asia  and in the Balkans [in Greek] (Athens: Domos, 1996). For the thirteenth and fourteenth  centuries, see George Georgiades Arnakis, The Early Osmanlis: A Contribution to the Problem  of the Fall of Hellenism in Asia Minor (1282–1337) [in Greek] (Athens: N. Frandjeskakis,  1947; repr., Athens: Archipelagos, 2008). Finally, Muslim reactions to the Byzantine defeat  at Mantzikert are covered in El Cheikh, Byzantium Viewed by the Arabs, pp. 178–181. Also  of value are the following studies by Speros Vryonis Jr.: “A Personal History of the History  of the Battle of Mantzikert,” in Byzantine Asia Minor (6th–12th cent.) (Athens: National  Hellenic Research Foundation/Institute for Byzantine Research, 1998), pp. 225–244; “The  Greek and Arabic Sources on the Battle of Mantzikert, 1071 A.D.,” in Byzantine Studies:  Essays on the Slavic World and the Eleventh Century, ed. Speros Vryonis Jr. (New Rochelle,  N.Y.: Aristide D. Caratzas, 1992), pp. 125–140; as well as Claude Cahen, “La campagne de  Mantzikert d’après les sources musulmanes,” Byzantion 9 (1934): 613–642.

99 Miguel Ataliates, Historia, ed. and parallel Spanish trans. Immaculada Pérez Martín  (Madrid: Consejo Superior de Investigaciones Científicas, 2002), pp. 144–145; Wladimir  Brunet de Presle and Immanuel Bekker, eds., Michaelis Attaliotae historia (Bonn: Weber,  1853), pp. 195–198. An English translation of Attaleiates’s History by Anthony Kaldellisand Dimitris Krallis for the Dumbarton Oaks Medieval Library series is currently in prepa ration. On Attaleiates’s views on the military disintegration of the Byzantine Empire, see  Speros Vryonis Jr., “The Eleventh Century: Was There a Crisis in the Empire? The Decline  of Quality and Quantity in the Byzantine Armed Forces,” in Vlyssidou, The Empire in Crisis  (?), pp. 17–43, 18–34. Attaleiates’s political ideas are discussed in Dimitris Krallis, Michael  Attaleiates and the Politics of Imperial Decline in Eleventh-Century Byzantium (Tempe: Ari zona Center for Medieval and Renaissance Studies, 2012); Krallis, “‘Democratic’ Action  in Eleventh-Century Byzantium: Michael Attaleiates’s ‘Republicanism’ in Context,” Viator 40 (2009): 35–53; Anthony Kaldellis, “A Byzantine Argument for the Equivalence of all  Religions: Michael Attaleiates on Ancient and Modern Romans,” International Journal of the  Classical Tradition 14 (2007): 1–20; and Alexander Kazhdan, Studies on Byzantine Literature  of the Eleventh and Twelfth Centuries (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; Paris: Édi tions de la Maison des Sciences de l’Homme, 1984), “The Social Views of Michael Atta leiates,” pp. 23–86.

100 The economic aspects of Byzantine decay are examined in Angeliki E. Laiou and  Cécile Morrisson, The Byzantine Economy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007),  pp. 228–230; and, in general, the studies by Angeliki E. Laiou, “Economic Thought and  Ideology,” and “The Byzantine Economy: An Overview,” both in The Economic History of  Byzantium: From the Seventh through the Fifteenth Century, ed. Angeliki E. Laiou (Washing

ton, D.C.: Dumbarton Oaks Research Library and Collection, 2002), pp. 1123–1144 and  1145–1164, respectively. Consider also Christos P. Baloglou, “Economic Thought in the  Last Byzantine Period,” in Ancient and Medieval Economic Ideas and Concepts of Social Justice, ed. S. Todd Lowry and Barry Gordon (Leiden: Brill, 1998), pp. 405–438; Alexander N. Dio medes, “Economic Vicissitudes of the Decaying Byzantium,” Revue des Sciences Économiques  et Financières 8 (1939): 277–303 [in Greek]. For heavy taxation as a cause of Byzantium’s  fall, see notably Peter Schreiner, “Zentralmacht und Steuerhölle. Die Steuerlast im Byzan tinischen Reich,” in Mit dem Zehnten fing es an: Eine Kulturgeschichte der Steuer, ed. Uwe  Schulze, 2n ed. (Munich: C. H. Beck, 1986), pp. 64–73. Critiques of monastic property  are discussed in Peter Charanis, “The Monastic Properties and the State in the Byzantine  Empire,” Dumbarton Oaks Papers 4 (1948): 53–118, repr. in Charanis, Social, Economic and  Political Life in the Byzantine Empire: Collected Studies (London: Variorum Reprints, 1973),  no. 1. On tax exemptions, see Nicolas Oikonomidès, Fiscalité et exemption fiscale à Byz ance (IXe-XIe s.) (Athens: National Hellenic Research Foundation/Institute for Byzantine  Research, 1996). Consider also Emili[o] Herman, “Zum kirchlichen Benefizialwesen im  Byzantinischen Reich,” Studia et Documenta Historiae et Iuris 3 (1937): 253–264. For lateByzantine debates on decline, see, e.g., Speros Vryonis Jr., “Crises and Anxieties in Fifteenth  Century Byzantium: The Reassertion of Old, and the Emergence of New Cultural Forms,”  in Islamic and Middle Eastern Societies, ed. Robert Olson (Brattleboro, Vt.: Amana Books,  1987), pp. 100–125; Jan-Louis van Dieten, “Politische Ideologie und Niedergang im Byzanz  der Palaiologen,” Zeitschrift für Historische Forschung 6 (1979): 1–35; Ihor Ševčenko, “The  Decline of Byzantium Seen through the Eyes of Its Intellectuals,” Dumbarton Oaks Papers 15 (1961): 169–186, repr. in Ševčenko, Society and Intellectual Life in Late Byzantium (Lon

don: Variorum Reprints, 1981), no. 2; Franz Dölger, “Politische und geistige Strömungen  im sterbenden Byzanz,” Jahrbuch der Österreichischen Byzantinisischen Gesellschaft 3 (1954):  3–18; Hans-Georg Beck, Theodoros Metochites, die Krise des byzantinischen Weltbildes im 14.  Jahrhundert (Munich: C. H. Beck, 1952).

101 The factors that led to the famine are surveyed in Angeliki Laiou, “The Provision ing of Constantinople during the Winter of 1306–1307,” Byzantion 37 (1967): 91–113. On  Andronikos’s rule in general, see Angeliki Laiou, Constantinople and the Latins: The Foreign  Policy of Andronicus II, 1282–1328 (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1972);  Ursula Victoria Bosch, Kaiser Andronikos III. Palaiologos: Versuch einer Darstellung der byzan tinischen Geschichte in den Jahren 1321–1341 (Amsterdam: A. M. Hakkert, 1965).

102 The Correspondence of Athanasius I, Patriarch of Constantinople: Letters to the Emperor  Andronicus II, Members of the Imperial Family, and Officials, ed., trans., and comm. Alice Mary Maffry Talbot (Washington, D.C.: Dumbarton Oaks Center for Byzantine Studies,  1975), Letter 93 (Greek text p. 242, English trans. p. 243). On Athanasios, see Correspon dence of Athanasius I, “General Introduction,” pp. xv–xxxi; as well as Emmanuel Patedakis,  “Athanasios I Patriarch of Constantinople (1289–1293, 1303–1309): A Critical Edition  with Introduction and Commentary of Selected Unpublished Works” (PhD diss., University  of Oxford, 2004); John L. Boojamra, The Church and Social Reform: The Policies of the Patri arch Athanasios of Constantinople (New York: Fordham University Press, 1993); Boojamra,  “Social Thought and Reforms of Athanasios of Constantinople (1289–1293; 1303–1309),”  Byzantion 55 (1985): 332–382; Boojamra, Church Reform in the Late Byzantine Empire: A  Study of the Patriarchate of Athanasios of Constantinople (Thessalonike: Patriarchal Institute  for Patristic Studies, 1982); Demetrios J. Constantelos, “Life and Social Welfare Activ ity of Patriarch Athanasios I (1289–1293, 1303–1309) of Constantinople,” in Byzantine  Ecclesiastical Personalities, ed. Nomikos M. Vaporis (= The Byzantine Fellowship Lectures;  2) (Brookline, Mass.: Holy Cross Orthodox Press, 1975), pp. 73–88; Klaus-Peter Matschke,  “Politik und Kirche im spätbyzantinischen Reich: Athanasios I., Patriarch von Konstanti nopel 1289–1293; 1303–1309,” Wissenschaftliche Zeitschrift der Karl-Marx-Universität Leipzig:  Gesellschafts- und Sprachwissenschaftliche Reihe 15 (1966): 479–486, repr. in Matschke, Das  spätbyzantinische Konstantinopel: Alte und neue Beiträge zur Stadtgeschichte zwischen 1261 und  1453 (Hamburg: Verlag Dr. Kovač, 2008), pp. 89–113; and with an eye to the relations  between Athanasios and Andronikos, Joseph Gill, “Emperor Andronikos II and the Patri- arch Athanasius I,” Byzantina 2 (1970): 13–19; and Nicolae Bănescu, “Le patriarche Atha nase Ier et Andronic II Paléologue: État religieux, politique et social de l’empire,” Académie  roumaine. Bulletin de la section historique 23 (1942): 28–56. Consider also Joseph Kalothetos’s  (fl. 1336–1341) biography of Athanasios: “Vios kai politeia tou en agiois patros ēmōn archi episkopou Kōnstantinoupoleōs Athanasiou,” in Ioseph Kalothetou Suggramata, ed. Demetrios 

G. Tsames (Thessalonike: Center for Byzantine Studies, 1980), pp. 453–502. 103 The Correspondence of Athanasius I Patriarch of Constantinople, Letter 65 (152/153). 104 Ibid., Letter 93 (242/243).

105 Ibid., Letter 68 (160 and 162/163 and 165). On the transportation of grain supplies  and food provisions in the Byzantine Empire, see Johannes Koder, “Maritime Trade and the  Food Supply for Constantinople in the Middle Ages,” in Travel in the Byzantine World, ed.  Ruth Makrides (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2002), pp. 109–124; John L. Teall, “The Grain Supply  of the Byzantine Empire, 330–1025,” Dumbarton Oaks Papers 13 (1959): 87–139; Georges  I. Brătianu [Bratianu], “Nouvelles contributions à l’étude de l’approvisionnement de Con

stantinople sous les Paléologues et les empereurs ottomans,” Byzantion 6 (1931): 641–656;  Brătianu, “La question de l’approvisionnement de Constantinople à l’époque byzantine et  ottomane,” Byzantion 5 (1929/30): 83–107.

106 The Correspondence of Athanasius I Patriarch of Constantinople, Letter 100 (256/257).  See also ibid., Letter 106 (266/267).

107 Ibid., Letter 106 (266/267).

108 Vasileios Syros, “Between Chimera and Charybdis: Byzantine and Post-Byzantine  Views on the Political Organization of the Italian City-States,” Journal of Early Modern  History 14 (2010): 451–504, 467–472; Angeliki E. Laiou, “Economic Concerns and Atti tudes of the Intellectuals of Thessalonike,” Dumbarton Oaks Papers 57 [= Symposium on Late  Byzantine Thessalonike] (2003): 205–223; Laiou, “Social Justice: Exchange and Prosperity in  Byzantium,” Proceedings of the Academy of Athens 74 (1999): 107–132 [in Greek]; Peter Cha ranis, “On the Social Structure and Economic Organization of the Byzantine Empire in the  Thirteenth Century and Later,” Byzantinoslavica 12:94–153, repr. in Charanis, Social, Eco nomic and Political Life in the Byzantine Empire, no. 4. On the Zealot revolution, see John W.  Barker, “Late Byzantine Thessalonike: A Second City’s Challenges and Responses,” Dumbar ton Oaks Papers 57 (2003): 5–33, esp. 14–21; Donald M. Nicol, The Reluctant Emperor: A  Biography of John Cantacuzene, Byzantine Emperor and Monk, c. 1295–1383 (Cambridge:  Cam bridge University Press, 1996), pp. 45–83; Konstantinos Kotsiopoulos, “The Zealots  of Thessalonike and their Popular Basis,” Ta Vyzantina 18 (1995/96): 277–284 [in Greek];  Klaus-Peter Matschke, “Thessalonike und die Zeloten: Bemerkungen zu einem Schlüssel ereignis der spätbyzantinischen Stadts- und Reichsgeschichte,” Byzantinoslavica 55 (1994): 19–43; Matschke, Fortschritt und Reaktion in Byzanz im 14. Jahrhundert: Konstantinopel in der  Bürgerkriegsperiode von 1341 bis 1354 (Berlin: Akademie-Verlag, 1971); Daphne Papadatou,  “Political Associations in the Late Byzantine Period: The Zealots and Sailors of Thessa lonica,” Balkan Studies 28 (1987): 3–23; Peter Charanis, “Internal Strife in Byzantium during  the Fourteenth Century,” Byzantion 15 (1941): 208–230, repr. in Charanis, Social, Economic  and Political Life in the Byzantine Empire, no. 6; Oreste Tafrali, Thessalonique au quatorzième  siècle (Paris: P. Geuthner, 1913; repr., Thessalonike: Idryma Meleton Hersonesou tou Aimou,  1993); and in general Günter Weiss, Johannes Kantakuzenos—Aristokrat, Staatsmann, Kaiser  und Mönch—in der Gesellschaftsentwicklung von Byzanz im 14. Jahrhundert (Wiesbaden: O.  Harrassowitz, 1969); Franz Dölger, “Johannes VI. Kantakuzenos als dynastischer Legitimist,”  Seminarium Kondakovianum 10 (1938): 19–30, repr. in Dölger, Παρασπορα: 30 Aufsätze zur  Geschichte, Kultur und Sprache des byzantinischen Reiches (Munich: Buch-Kunstverlag Ettal,  1961), pp. 194–207. On the intellectual life of late Byzantine Thessalonike, consult Costas  N. Constantinides, “The Origin of the Flourishing of Learning in Thessaloniki during the  Fourteenth Century,” Dodonē 21 (1992): 133–150 [in Greek]; Daniele Bianconi, Tessalonica  nell’età dei Paleologi: Le pratiche intellettuali nel riflesso della cultura scritta (Centre d’études  byzantines, néo-helléniques et sud-esteuropéennes, École des Hautes Études en Sciences  Sociales, 2005); Franz Tinnefeld, “Intellectuals in Late Byzantine Thessalonike,” Dumbarton  Oaks Papers 57 (2003): 153–172; Vassilis Katsaros, “Literary and Intellectual Life in Byzan tine Thessaloniki,” in Queen of the Worthy: Thessaloniki, History and Culture, ed. Ioannes K.  Hassiotis (Thessalonike: Paratiritis, 1997), pp. 305–332; Constantine N. Constantinides,  “The Beginnings of the Intellectual Acme in Thessalonike in the 14th Century,” Dōdōnē 21 (1992): 133–150 [in Greek]; Ioannes E. Anastasios, “Education in Thessalonike in the 14th  Century,” Vuzantina 13 (1985): 909–921 [in Greek]; Donald M. “Thessalonica as a Cultural  Centre in the Fourteenth Century,” in Ē Thessalonikē metaxu Anatolēs kai Duseos (Thessa

lonike: Etaireia Makedonikōn Spoudōn, 1982), pp. 121–131, repr. in Nicol, Studies in Late  Byzantine History and Prosopography (London: Variorum Reprints, 1986), no. 10; as well as  the articles in Macedonia during the Palaeologan Era (Thessalonike: Aristotle University of  Thessalonike, 1992), esp. Basiliki Papoulia, “Intellectual Currents in Macedonia during the  Fourteenth Century” (pp. 63–73) and Alkmini Stavridou-Zafraka, “The Physiognomy of  Thessalonike as the Second City of the Byzantine Empire during the Palaeologan Era” (pp.  75–84) [both in Greek].

109 Jean F. Boissonade, Anecdota græca e codicibus regiis (Paris: Excusum in Regio Typog rapheo, 1830; repr., Hildesheim: Olms, 1962), 2:137–187.

110 On Choumnos, see Ihor Ševčenko, Études sur la polémique entre Théodore Métochite  et Nicéphore Choumnos: La vie intellectuelle et politique à Byzance sous les premiers Paléologues (Brussels: Byzantion, 1962); and Jean Verpeaux, Nicéphore Choumnos: Homme d’État et  humaniste byzantin (ca 1250/1255–1327) (Paris: A. et J. Picard, 1959). 111 Verpeaux, Nicéphore Choumnos, p. 35.

112 Tinnefeld, “Intellectuals in Late Byzantine Thessalonike,” p. 165.

113 Boissonade, Anecdota græca e codicibus regiis, 2:168–169. See also Zakythinos, Crise  monétaire et crise économique à Byzance, pp. 46–47.

114 The text was first edited by Vasileios Laourdas, “Thoma Magistrou Tois Thessaloni keusi peri omonoias,” Epistēmonikē Epetēris Scholēs Nomikōn kai Oikonomikōn Epistēmōn Aris toteleiou Panepistēmiou Thessalonikēs 12 (1969): 751–775, 753–768, and has been reprinted  with facing modern Greek translation (pp. 66–115) and commentary (pp. 116–140) in  Sotiria Triantari-Mara, The Political Thought of Fourteenth Century in Thessaloniki: Oration to  the Thessalonicans on Concord by Thomas Magistros; an Approach on the Contribution of Politi cal Philosophy to Modern Times (Athens: Herodotos, 2002). Surveys of Magister’s life and  oeuvre include Sotiria A. Triantari, Politics, Rhetoric and Communication in the Fourteenth  and the Twenty-first Century: Oration about Kingdom and about State of Thomas Magistros [in Greek] (Thessalonike: A. Stamoulis, 2009), pp. 17–37; Bianconi, Tessalonica nell’età dei  Paleologi, pp. 72–90; and Stephanos K. Skalistes, Thomas Magistros: His Life and Œuvre [in  Greek] (Thessalonike: Aristotle University of Thessaloniki, 1984).

115 For Magister’s contribution to the reception and study of the classical legacy,  see Niels Gaul, Thomas Magistros und die spätbyzantische Sophistik: Studien zum Humanis mus urbaner Eliten in der frühen Palaiologenzeit (Wiesbaden: O. Harrassowitz, 2011); Gaul,  “Moschopulos, Lopadiotes, Phrankopulos (?), Magistros, Staphidakes: Prosopographisches  und Methodologisches zur Lexikographie des frühen 14. Jahrhunderts,” Super alta perennis  4 (2008): 163–196, 184–190; Gaul, “The Twitching Shroud: Collective Construction of  Paideia in the Circle of Thomas Magistros,” Segno e Testo 5 (2007): 263–340; Vasileios Laour das, “Classical Philology in Thessalonike in the Fourteenth Century,” Etaireia Makedonikōn  Spoudōn. Idruma Meletōn Hersonesou tou Aimou 37 (1960): 5–20 [in Greek]. On lateByzantine philologists in general, see Sophia Mergiali, L’Enseignement et les Lettrés [sic] pen dant l’époque des Paléologues (1261–1453) (Athens: Société des Amis du Peuple, Centre  d’Études Byzantines, 1996), pp. 49–59.

116 There is no scholarly consensus as to which of the two events Magister is referring  to. I am inclined to the view that Magister alludes to both the conflict between Andronikos  II and his grandson Andronikos III and the events that precipitated the Zealot revolt. For  a similar interpretation and review of previous scholarship, see Triantari-Mara, The Political  Thought of Fourteenth Century in Thessaloniki, pp. 37–53. On the conflict between Androni

kos II and his grandson, see Nicol, The Last Centuries of Byzantium, chap. “The Question  of the Succession and the First Civil War,” pp. 151–166; as well as Leonidas Mavrommatis,  The First Palaiologoi: Problems of Political Praxis and Ideology (Athens: Syllogos pros Diadosin  ton Hellenikon Grammaton, 1983), pp. 52–78; Konstantinos P. Kyrris, Byzantium in the 14th  Century (Nicosia: Lampousa, 1982) [both in Greek].

117 Patrologia Græca; 145, ed. Jacques-Paul Migne (Paris: J.-P. Migne and Garnier,  1904), pp. 447–495 and 495–547; partial English trans. in Social and Political Thought in  Byzantium, from Justinian I to the Last Palaeologus; Passages from Byzantine Writers and Docu ments, trans. Ernest Barker (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1957), pp. 163–168 and 168–173,  respectively; modern Greek trans. and commentary in Triantari, Politics, Rhetoric and Com munication in the Fourteenth and the Twenty-First Century, pp. 166–403; Italian trans. Toma  Magistro, La regalità, ed. and trans. Paola Volpe Cacciatore (Naples: M. D’Auria, 1997).  Scholarly treatments of Magister’s political ideas include: Sotiria [A.] Triantari[-Mara], Poli tics, Rhetoric and Communication in the Fourteenth and the Twenty-first Century, pp. 75–164;  Triantari, The Political Views of Byzantine Thinkers from Tenth to Thirteenth Century (Thessa lonike: Herodotos, 2002), pp. 167–257; Triantari, “Political Views in Thomas More’s Utopia and Thomas Magistros’s On Kingship and On the State,” Parnassos 44 (2002): 317–338 [all  in Greek]; Christos P. Baloglou, “Thomas Magistros’ Vorschläge zur Wirtschafts- und Sozi alpolitik,” Byzantinoslavica 60 (1999): 60–70; Ioannis G. Leontiadis, “Untersuchungen zum  Staatsverständnis der Byzantiner aufgrund der Fürsten- bzw. Untertanenspiegel (13. bis 15.  Jahrhundert)” (PhD diss., University of Vienna, 1997), pp. 107–149; Léon-Pierre Raybaud, Le gouvernement et l’administration centrale de l’empire byzantin sous les premiers Paléologues  (1258–1354) (Paris: Sirey, 1968), pp. 24–35. For a study that situates Magister in the history  of late Byzantine advice literature, see Konstantinos D. S. Paidas, The Byzantine Mirrors of  Princes of the Late Period (1254–1403): Expressions of the Byzantine Royal Ideal [in Greek]  (Athens: Grigoris, 2006).

118 Ihor Ševčenko, “Alexios Makrembolites and His Dialogue between the Rich and the  Poor,” in Zbornik Radova Vizantološkog Instituta 6 (1960): 187–228, 213, 225, repr. in Šev čenko, Society and Intellectual Life in Late Byzantium (London: Variorum Reprints, 1981),  no. 7. Makrembolites’s social ideas are discussed also in Dimitrios G. Magriplis, “Sociologi cal Approaches to Byzantine History: Conclusions from the Study of Alexios Makremvoli tis’ Dialogue between the Rich and the Poor (14th Century),” Vyzantinos Domos 15 (2006):  107–124 [in Greek]; Klaus-Peter Matschke and Franz Tinnefeld, Die Gesellschaft im späten  Byzanz: Gruppen, Strukturen und Lebensformen (Cologne: Böhlau, 2001), pp. 344–347; Eva  de Vries-van der Velden, L’élite byzantine devant l’avance turque à l’époque de la guerre civile  de 1341 à 1354 (Amsterdam: J. C. Gieben, 1989), pp. 251–289; and Costas P. Kyrres, “Elé ments traditionnels et éléments révolutionnaires dans l’idéologie d’Aléxios Makrembolitès  et d’autres intellectuels byzantins du XIVe s.,” in Actes du XIVe Congrès International des  Etudes Byzantines (Bucharest: Editura Academiei Republicii Socialiste România, 1975),  2:177–188.

119 Rodolphe Guilland, “Le Traité inédit ‘sur l’usure’ de Nicolas Cabasilas,” in Eis  mnēmēn Spyridōnos Lamprou (Athens: Epitropē Ekdoseōs tōn kataloipōn Spyridōnos Lam prou, 1935), pp. 269–277, 274; Laiou, “Economic Concerns and Attitudes of the Intellectu als of Thessalonike,” p. 217; Matschke and Tinnefeld, Die Gesellschaft im späten Byzanz, pp.  347–349. See further Marie-Hélène Congourdeau, “Hésychasme et palamisme,” in Histoire  du christianisme, vol. 6, Un temps d’épreuves (1274–1453) (Paris: G. Beauchesne, 1990), pp.  557–563, 508–510; Christos P. Baloglou, “Kavasilas’ Economic Thought,” Byzantiaka 16 (1996): 191–213 [in Greek]; as well as Niketas Siniossoglou, Radical Platonism in Byzantium:  Illumination and Utopia in Gemistos Plethon (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011),  pp. 359–369; Peter Charanis, “Observations on the ‘Anti-Zealot’ Discourse of Cabasilas,”  Revue des Etudes Sud-Est Européennes 9 (1971): 369–376, repr. in Charanis, Social, Economic  and Political Life in the Byzantine Empire, no. 7. For Kavasilas’s life and works, consult Marie Hélène Congourdeau, Correspondance de Nicolas Cabasilas (Paris: Les Belles Lettres, 2010),  pp. xi–xvii; Yannis Spiteris and Carmelo G. Conticello, “Nicola Cabasilas Chamaetos,” in La  Théologie byzantine et sa tradition, vol. 2, XIIIe–XIXe s., ed. Carmelo G. Conticello and Vassa  Conticello (Turnhout: Brepols, 2002), pp. 315–410; Yannis Spiteris and Patrizia Morelli,  Cabasilas, teologo e mistico bizantino: Nicola Cabasilas Chamaetos, e la sua sintesi teologica (Rome:  Lipa, 1996); Constantine N. Tsirpanlis, “The Career and Writings of Nicolas Cabasilas,”Byzantion 49 (1979): 414–427; George T. Dennis, “Nicholas Cabasilas Chamaëtos and His  Discourse on Abuses Committed by Authorities against Sacred Things,” Byzantine Studies/ Études Byzantines 5 (1978): 80–87, repr. in Dennis, Byzantium and the Franks, 1350–1420 (London: Variorum Reprints, 1982), no. 11; Horst Müller-Asshoff, “Beobachtungen an den  Hauptschriften des Gregorios Palamas und Nikolaos Kabasilas,” Byzantinische Zeitschrift 70 (1977): 22–41; Athanasios A. Angelopoulos, Nikolaos Kavasilas Chamaetos, His Life and  Work (A Contribution to Macedonian Byzantine Prosopography) [in Greek] (Thessalonike:  Patriarchal Institute for Patristic Studies, 1970); Sévérien Salaville, “Quelques précisions  pour la biographie de Nicolas Cabasilas,” in Proceedings of the Ninth International Congress of  Byzantine Studies (Athens: Myrtides, 1958), 3:215–226; as well as the following studies by  Ihor Ševčenko: “Nicolas Cabasilas’ ‘Anti-Zealot’ Discourse: A Reinterpretation,” Dumbar ton Oaks Papers 11 (1957): 81–171; “The Author’s Draft of Nicolas Cabasilas’ ‘Anti-Zealot’  Discourse in Parisinus Gr. 1276,” Dumbarton Oaks Papers 14 (1960): 181–201; “A Postcript  on Nicolas Cabasilas’ ‘Anti-Zealot’ Discourse,” Dumbarton Oaks Papers 16 (1962): 403–408,  all three repr. in Ševčenko, Society and Intellectual Life in Late Byzantium, nos. 6, 5, and 4,  respectively. A survey of Byzantine attitudes to interest appears in Lazaros T. Houmanidis, 

“On Usury during the Byzantine Era,” Vuzantinai Meletai 6 (1995): 104–122 [in Greek]. 120 Patrologia Graeca 150: 727–750. See also Laiou, “Economic Concerns and Attitudes  of the Intellectuals of Thessalonike,” p. 213; Matschke and Tinnefeld, Die Gesellschaft im  späten Byzanz, pp. 349–355.

121 Laiou, “Economic Concerns and Attitudes of the Intellectuals of Thessalonike,” p.  215.

122 For further references and discussion, see Jonathan Harris, “Laonikos Chalkokon dyles and the Rise of Ottoman Turks,” Byzantine and Modern Greek Studies 27 (2003): 153– 170; Harris, “The Influence of Plethon’s Idea of Fate on the Historian Laonikos Chalko kondyles,” in Proceedings of the International Congress on Plethon and His Time, Mystras, ed. Linos G. Benakis and Christos P. Baloglou (Athens: International Society of Plethonian  and Byzantine Studies, 2003), pp. 211–217. Eschatological interpretations of Byzantine  decay are discussed in Siniossoglou, Radical Platonism in Byzantium, pp. 356–361; Paul Mag dalino, “The End of Time in Byzantium,” in Endzeiten: Eschatologie in den monotheistischen  Weltreligionen, ed. Wolfram Brandes and Felicitas Schmieder (Berlin: W. de Gruyter, 2008),  pp. 119–133, esp. 132–133; Magdalino, “The History of the Future and Its Uses: Proph ecy, Policy and Propaganda,” in The Making of Byzantine History, ed. Roderick Beaton and  Charlotte Roueché (Aldershot: Variorum, 1993), pp. 3–34; Marie-Hélène Congourdeau,  “Byzance et la fin du monde. Courants de pensée apocalyptiques sous les Paléologues, in  Les traditions apocalyptiques au tournant de la chute de Constantinople, ed. Benjamin Lellouch  and Stéphane Yerasimos (Paris: Harmattan, 2000), pp. 55–97; Agostino Pertusi, Fine di  Bisanzio e fine del mondo: Significato e ruolo storico delle profezie sulla caduta di Costantinopoli in  Oriente e in Occidente, ed. Enrico Morini (Rome: Nella Sede dell’Istituto Palazzo Borromini,  1988); Gerhard Podkalsky, “Der Fall Konstantinopels in der Sicht der Reichsechatologie  und der Klagelieder. Vorahnungen und Reaktionen,” Archiv für Kulturgeshichte 57 (1975):  71–86; Podkalsky, Byzantinische Reichseschatologie: Die Periodisierung der Weltgeschichte in den  vier Grossreichen (Daniel 2 und 7) und dem tausendjährigen Friedensreiche (Apok. 20): Eine  motivgeschichtliche Untersuchung (Munich: W. Fink, 1972); C. J. G. Turner, “Pages from Late  Byzantine Philosophy of History,” Byzantinische Zeitschrift 57 (1964): 346–373; and Alex

ander A. Vasiliev, “Medieval Ideas on the End of the World: West and East,” Byzantion 16 (1942/3): 462–502.

123 Exhortatory Address to Despot Theodore about the Peloponnese—Spyridon P. Lam pros, Palaiologeia kai Peloponnēsiaka (Athens: V. N. Gregoriades, 1972), 4:113–135—par tial English trans. in Barker, Social and Political Thought in Byzantium, pp. 207–212. Com pare the nineteenth-century English translation by the Scottish historian George Finlay 

(1799–1875) in Christos P. Baloglou, “George Finlay and Georgios Gemistos Plethon. New  Evidence from Finlay’s Records,” Medioevo greco 3 (2003): 23–42, 26–35, repr. in Baloglou,  Mele tē mata peri Geōrgiou Gemistou-Plēthōnos (Athens: Eptalofos, 2011), pp. 100–119. For  further discussion of Pletho’s memoranda, see Siniossoglou, Radical Platonism in Byzantium,

part 3, “Mistra versus Athos,” pp. 327–392; Giorgio Gemisto Pletone, Trattato delle virtù, intro., Italian trans., notes, and apparatuses Moreno Neri (Milan: Bompiani, 2010), pp.  47–73; Peter Garnsey, “Gemistus Plethon and Platonic Political Philosophy,” in Transfor mations of Late Antiquity, ed. Philip Rousseau and Manolis Papoutsakis (Farnham: Ash gate, 2009), pp. 327–340, esp. 334–338; Christos P. Baloglou, Georgiou Gemistou Plēthōnos  peri Peloponnēsiakōn pragmatōn (Athens: Eleftheri Skepsis, 2002), pp. 97–127; Proceedings  of the Inter national Congress on Plethon and His Time, esp. Savvas P. Spentzas, “The Mili tary Organization of the Peloponnese: G. Gemistos Plethon’s Economic, Social and Fis cal Proposals,” (pp. 243–265) [in Greek]; Anastassios D. Karayiannis, “Georgios Gemistos  Plethon on Economic Policy,” (pp. 306–310); Christos P. Baloglou, “The Institutions of  Ancient Sparta in the Work of Pletho,” (pp. 311–326; first published as “The Institutions of  Ancient Sparta in the Work of Pletho,” Antike und Abendland 51 [2005]: 137–149); Yannis  Smarnakis, “A Contribution to the Archaeology of Modern Utopian Thought: History and  Utopia in Plethon’s Oeuvre,” Historein 7 (2007): 103–113, esp. 106–109; Vryonis, “Crises  and Anxieties in Fifteenth Century Byzantium,” pp. 120–122; Christopher M. Woodhouse, George Gemistos Plethon: The Last of the Hellenes (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986; repr.,  2000), pp. 92–109; N. Patrick Peritore, “The Political Thought of Gemistos Plethon: A  Renaissance Byzantine Reformer,” Polity 10 (1977): 168–191; Johannes Irmscher, “Die  Wandlungen der Staatsidee im ausgehenden Byzanz,” Rivista di cultura classica e medioevale

19 (1977): 446–450; J. Duncan M. Derret, “Gemistus Plethon, the Essenes, and More’s  Utopia,” Bibliothèque d’Humanisme et Renaissance 27 (1965): 579–606; John Mamalakis,  “The Impact of Contemporary Events on George Gemistos’ Ideas,” in Proceedings of the  Ninth International Congress of Byzantine Studies, ed. S. Kyriakides et al. [in Greek] (Athens:  Typographeion Myrtidi, 1956), 2:498–532, esp. 504–511; Johannes Draseke, “Plethons und  Bessarions Denkschriften über die Angelegenheiten im Peloponnes,” Neue Jahrbücher für  das klassische Altertum, Geschichte und deutsche Literatur 27 (1911): 102–119; and Henry F.  Tozer, “A Byzantine Reformer,” Journal of Hellenic Studies 7 (1886): 353–380.

124 Georgios Gemistos to Manuel Palaeologus concerning the Affairs in the Peloponnese— Lampros, Palaiologeia kai Peloponnēsiaka, 3:246–265—partial English trans. in Barker, Social  and Political Thought in Byzantium, pp. 198–206. Consider also Finlay’s translation in Balo glou, “George Finlay and Georgios Gemistos Plethon,” pp. 36–42.

125 Lampros, Palaiologeia kai Peloponnēsiaka, 3:263. Plethon’s economic ideas are dis cussed in Christos P. Baloglou, “Economic Thought in the Last Byzantine Period,” pp.  405–438, 424–430; Baloglou, Georgios Gemistos-Plethon: Ökonomisches Denken in der spät byzantinischen Geisteswelt (Athens: Historical Publications St. D. Basilopoulos, 1998); Sav vas P. Spentzas, G. Gemistos Plethon, the Philosopher of Mystra: His Economic, Social and Fiscal  Views [in Greek] (Athens: Ekdoseis M. Kardamitsa, 1987).

126 Bernard Lewis, What Went Wrong? The Clash between Islam and Modernity in the  Middle East (New York: Perennial, 2003), chap. “Modernization and Social Equality,” pp.  82–95.

127 Lewis, What Went Wrong?, chap. “Secularism and the Civil Society,” pp. 96–116. 128 See, for example, the following two collections of essays edited by Peter F. Bang and  Christopher A. Bayly: Tributary Empires in Global History (Houndmills: Palgrave Macmil lan, 2011) and Tributary Empires in History: Comparative Perspectives from Antiquity to the  Late Medieval [= The Medieval History Journal 6, no. 2 (2003)]. The comparative study of the  Roman, Mughal, and Ottoman empires is the subject of the international research project  “Tributary Empires Compared” at the SAXO Institute at the University of Copenhagen. A  comparative investigation of the decline of the Ottoman, Safavid, and Mughal empires can  be found in Rohan D’Souza, “Crisis before the Fall: Some Speculations on the Decline of  the Ottomans, Safavids and Mughals,” Social Scientist 30 (2002): 3–30. See also in general:  Stephen F. Dale, The Muslim Empires of the Ottomans, Safavids, and Mughals (Cambridge:  Cambridge University Press, 2010); Francis Robinson, “Ottomans-Safavids-Mughals:  Shared Knowledge and Connective Systems,” Journal of Islamic Studies 8 (1997): 151–184;  Halil Berktay, “Three Empires and the Societies they Governed: Iran, India and the Otto man Empire,” Journal of Peasant Studies 18 (1992) [= New Approaches to State and Peasant  in Otto man History, ed. Halil Berktay and Suraiya Faroqhi]: 247–263; İ. Metin Kunt, “The  Later Muslim Empires: Ottomans, Safavids, Mughals,” in Islam: The Religious and Political  Life of a World Community, ed. Marjorie Kelly (New York: Praeger, 1984), pp. 113–136.

Post a Comment

Previous Post Next Post